184
Views
0
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Research Article

L9-free groups

, ORCID Icon &
Pages 2815-2851 | Received 18 Jul 2023, Accepted 15 Jan 2024, Published online: 05 Feb 2024

Abstract

In this article we classify all L9-free finite groups.

2020 MATHEMATICS SUBJECT CLASSIFICATION:

Introduction

There are some algebraic laws that hold in a lattice L if and only if L does not have a sublattice of a specific shape. For example, a lattice is modular if and only if it does not have a sublattice isomorphic to the so-called pentagon L5.

If L is a lattice, then we call a group L-free if and only if its subgroup lattice does not contain a lattice isomorphic to L. For example, the finite L5-free groups are exactly the modular groups, and these have been classified by Iwasawa in 1941, see [Citation4]. The subgroup lattice of the dihedral group of order 8, often denoted by L10, and some of its sublattices are of particular interest. One reason is that, if p is a prime number, then a finite p-group is L5-free if and only if it is L10-free.

There are several sublattices of L10 containing L5:

In 1999 Baginski and Sakowicz [Citation2] studied finite groups that are L6-free and L7-free at the same time, and later Schmidt [Citation8] classified the finite groups that are L6- or L7-free. Together with Andreeva and the first author he also characterized, in [Citation1], all finite groups that are L8-free or M8-free. Finally, the finite M9-free groups have been classified by Pölzing and the second author in [Citation6]. Furthermore, there is a general discussion of L10-free groups by Schmidt, which can be found in [Citation9] and [Citation10].

In this paper we investigate finite L9-free groups. Since L9 is a sublattice of L10, the groups that we consider are L10-free and therefore we can use Corollary C in [Citation9] as a starting point for our analysis: Every finite L10-free group G has normal Hall subgroups N1N2 such that N1=PSyl(G)|PEGN2/N1 is a 2-group and G/N2 is meta-cyclic.

Our strategy is to choose N:=N1 maximal with respect to the above constraints, and then we show that N has a complement K that is a direct and coprime product of groups of the following structure: cyclic groups, groups isomorphic to Q8 or semi-direct products QR, where Q has prime order and R is cyclic of prime-power order such that 1Φ(R)=CQ(R). Furthermore, [N,K]CN(K) is a 2-group and CO2(N)(K) is cyclic or elementary abelian of order 4 and every Sylow subgroup of [N,K] is elementary abelian or isomorphic to Q8. If the action of K on N satisfies some more conditions, then we say that NK is in class L.

The aim of our article is to prove the following theorem:

Main Theorem. A finite group is in class L if and only if it is L9-free.

Notation and preliminary results

In this article we mostly follow the notation from Schmidt’s book [Citation7] and from [Citation5]. All groups considered are finite and G always denotes a finite group, moreover p and q always denote prime numbers. We quickly recall some standard concepts:

L(G) denotes the subgroup lattice of G, consisting of the set of subgroups of G with inclusion as the partial ordering. The infimum of two elements A,BL(G) is AB (their intersection) and the supremum is AB=A,B (the subgroup generated by A and B).

If L is any lattice, then G is said to be L-free if and only if L(G) does not have any sub-lattice that is isomorphic to L.

A lattice L is said to be modular if and only if for all X,Y,ZL such that XZ, the following (also called the modular law) is true: (XY)Z=X(YZ). We say that a group G is modular if and only if L(G) is modular.

The modular law is similar to Dedekind’s law (see 1.1.11 of [Citation5]). For all X,Y,ZG such that XZ it says that XYZ=X(YZ). We will use Dedekind’s law frequently throughout this article without giving an explicit reference each time.

If NG, then we say that an element gG induces power automorphisms on N if and only if Ug=U for all subgroups U of N. Furthermore PotG(N):={gG|Ug=U f.a.UN} is a subgroup of G because PotG(N)=UNNG(U).

Lemma 1.1.

Let K be a finite group that acts coprimely on the p-group P. Then P=[P,K]CP(K). If P is abelian, then this product is direct. If [P,K]Φ(P), then [P,K]=1. Furthermore [P,K]=[P,K,K] and for all K-invariant normal subgroups N of P we have that CP/N(K)=CP(K)N/N.

Proof.

These statements are a collection from 8.2.2, 8.2.7, 8.2.9, and 8.4.2 of [Citation5]. □

Lemma 1.2.

Let pπ(G) and suppose that G = PK, where P is a normal Sylow p-subgroup of G, KG is a p-group and P0:=[P,K]1. Suppose further that Φ(P0)CP(K) and that K acts irreducibly on P0/Φ(P0). If gPCP(K), then P0[g,K],Kg,K.

Proof.

Let gPCP(K) and R:=[g,K],K. Then we first remark that Rg,K. Lemma 1.1 shows that P=CP(K)P0 and hence we have elements cCP(K) and hP0 such that g = ch. We note that P0 EG and therefore Φ(P0) is a normal subgroup of G, moreover P0 is a p-group and hence P0/Φ(P0) is elementary abelian. Let :GG/Φ(P0) denote the natural homomorphism. As P0¯=[P¯,K¯] is abelian and K¯ acts coprimely on it, we see that C[P¯,K¯](K¯)[P¯,K¯,K¯]=1, again by Lemma 1.1. Therefore C[P¯,K¯](K¯)=C[P¯,K¯,K¯](K¯)=1. We recall that ch=gCP(K) and thus hCP(K), and then by hypothesis hΦ(P0) and in particular 1h¯P0¯. It follows that [h¯,K¯]1 because C[P¯,K¯](K¯)=1, see above. We conclude that 1[h¯,K¯]=[g¯,K¯]=[g,K]¯P0¯R¯. By hypothesis K acts irreducibly on P0¯, hence K¯ does as well and we see that P0¯=P0RΦ(P0)¯=(P0R)Φ(P0)¯. The main property of the Frattini subgroup (see for example 5.2.3 in [Citation5]) finally gives that P0=P0R. □

Lemma 1.3.

Let Q be a 2-group that is elementary abelian, cyclic or isomorphic to Q8. Then Q does not admit power automorphisms of odd order.

Proof.

If Q is abelian, then the assertion follows from 2.2.5 of [Citation5]. If QQ8, then Aut(Q)Sym4, and any automorphism of order 3 interchanges the maximal subgroups of Q. □

Lemma 1.4.

Suppose that G = NK, where N is a normal Hall subgroup of G and K is a complement. Let N1,N2NQ,RK and xN. Then the following hold:

  1. If N1Q and N2Rx are subgroups of G, then N1QN2Rx=N1(QR)N2(QR)x.

  2. If N2RxG and xQRN2=1, then QN2Rx=QRxCQR(x).

  3. If K is abelian and acts irreducibly on the abelian group N/Φ(N) or if N is abelian and K induces power automorphisms on it, then CK(N)=CK(x) or xΦ(N).

  4. If QR, then Q,Rx=[x,Q]RxRx.

Proof.

Suppose that N1Q and N2Rx are subgroups of G.

For (a) we do the following calculation: N1QN2Rx=(N1QNQ)N2Rx=N1Q(NQN2Rx)=N1QN2(NQxRx)=N1QN2(NQx(KxRx))=N1QN2((NQxKx)Rx)=N1QN2(QxRx)=N1Q(N(QR)xN2(QR)x)=(N1QN(QR))N2(QR)x=N1(QN(QR))N2(QR)x=N1((QK)N(QR))N2(QR)x=N1(Q(KN(QR)))N2(QR)x=N1(Q(QR))N2(QR)x=N1(QR)N2(QR)x.

Then (a) yields that QN2Rx=(QR)N2(QR)x. Therefore, if xQRN2=1 and if a,bQR and yN2 are such that a=ybx=yx1xb1b, then the fact that ab1=yx1xb1KN=1 implies that a = b and that y1=[x,b1]N2xQR=1. We deduce that a=bx=axQRx and that [x,a]=1. Hence QN2Rx=(QR)N2(QR)x=QRxCQR(x). This is (b).

If K is abelian, then xCN(CK(x)) and CN(CK(x)) is K-invariant. Thus, if K acts irreducibly on N/Φ(N) and xΦ(N), then CN(CK(x))Φ(N)=N, and the fact that [CK(x),N]=1 implies that CK(x)=CK(N). If K induces power automorphisms on the abelian group N, then 1.5.4 of [Citation7] implies that these are universal. If x = 1, then xΦ(N), and otherwise x1 and every element of K that centralizes x also centralizes N. Altogether (c) holds.

Suppose finally that QR. Then, for all gQ, we have that g=gx·(g1)x·gRx[x,Q][x,Q]RxRx. It follows that Q,Rx[x,Q]RxRx.

On the other hand (g1)xQxRx for all gQ and therefore [x,g]=(g1)xgQ,Rx.

This implies that [x,Q]Q,Rx. Since RxQ,Rx, we deduce that [x,Q]RxRxQ,Rx, which is (d). □

2 Battens and batten groups

Definition 2.1.

  1. We say that G is a batten if and only if G is a cyclic p-group, or isomorphic to Q8, or G = QR, where Q is a normal subgroup of prime order and R is a cyclic p-group of order coprime to |Q| and such that CR(Q)=Φ(R)1.

  2. We say that G is a batten group if and only if G is a direct product of battens of pairwise coprime order.

  3. If G is a batten group, then we say that BG is a batten of G if and only if B is a batten that is one of the direct factors of G.

Warning: It is possible for a subgroup of a batten group G to be a batten, abstractly, but not to be a batten of G. This can happen when it is a p-subgroup for some prime p of a batten as in the third case of Definition 2.1.

Example 2.2.

  1. Suppose that Q:=x is a group of order 19 and that R=y is a subgroup of Aut(X) of order 27. Further suppose that xy:=x7. Then B:=QR is a non-nilpotent batten. For this we calculate that xy3=(x7)y2=(x49)y=(x11)y=x77=x. Then the fact that xy=x7x implies that CR(Q)=y3=Φ(R). We note that B is a batten group and that Q is a subgroup of B that is a batten, but not a batten of B because [Q,R]1.

  2. Let B = QR be as in (a), let TQ8 and let S be a cyclic group of order 625. Then B×T×S is a batten group.

Remark 2.3.

Let G be a batten group and let B be a batten of G such that |π(B)|=2.

  1. B is not nilpotent, but B has a unique normal Sylow subgroup.

  2. A Sylow subgroup Q of B is cyclic, and therefore Q is batten. But Q is not a direct factor of G and hence Q is not a batten of G.

Definition 2.4.

Suppose that G is a non-nilpotent batten. Then there is a unique prime qπ(G) such that G has a normal Sylow q-subgroup Q, and Q is cyclic of order q. In this case we set B(G):=Q.

From the definition we can immediately see that B(G) is a characteristic subgroup of a non-nilpotent batten G and that it has prime order.

Lemma 2.5.

Suppose that G is a non-nilpotent batten, that rπ(G) and that RSylr(G) has order at least r 2. Then Z(G)=CR(B(G))=Φ(R)=Or(G).

Proof.

Since |R|r2, we see that RB(G). Then Definition 2.1 implies that R is cyclic and that there is a prime qπ(G){r} such that Q:=B(G)Sylq(G).

Now G=QR and CR(B(G))=Φ(R). We recall that R is cyclic, and then this implies that Φ(R)Z(G). Since G is not nilpotent, we see that B(G) is not contained in Z(G). Thus Z(G) is an r-group, because B(G) has prime order. In addition RZ(G), because G is not nilpotent. Since Φ(R) is a maximal subgroup of the cyclic group R, it follows that Φ(R)=Z(G). Moreover we have that [Q,Or(G)]QR=1, whence Or(G)CR(Q)=Φ(R)=Z(G)CR(Q). This proves all statements. □

Lemma 2.6.

If G is a batten group and PG is a Sylow p-subgroup of G for some prime p, then G has a subgroup of order p. In addition, Ω1(P)Z(G) or there is some non-nilpotent batten B of G such that Ω1(P)=P=B(B).

Proof.

Since PG, it follows that P is cyclic or isomorphic to Q8. Therefore Ω1(P) has order p.

If P is a batten, then Ω1(P)Z(P)Z(G). In particular Ω1(P) is the unique subgroup of G of its order. Otherwise there is a non-nilpotent batten B of G such that PB. If P has order p, then P=Ω1(P)=B(B) is a normal subgroup of B and so of G. Again Ω1(P) is the unique subgroup of K of order q. Otherwise we have that Ω1(P)Φ(P)=Z(B)Z(G) by Lemma 2.5. In particular Ω1(P) is the unique subgroup of K of its order. □

Lemma 2.7.

Suppose that H is a batten and that UH. Then U is a cyclic batten group. Furthermore, all subgroups of batten groups are batten groups.

Proof.

Assume for a contradiction that U is not a cyclic batten group. Then U is not a cyclic batten, and therefore H is neither cyclic of prime power order nor isomorphic to Q8. Thus H is not nilpotent, in particular |π(H)|=2 and all Sylow subgroups of H are cyclic. This implies that U is not a p-group. Let π(H)={q,r}, let Q:=B(H) and RSylr(H) be such that H = QR and CR(Q)=Φ(R)1. Now π(U)={q,r} as well and therefore B(H)U. Then Dedekind’s law gives that U=B(H)·(UR) is a proper subgroup of H=B(H)·R, and it follows that UR is a proper subgroup of R. In particular, since R is cyclic, we have that 1URΦ(R). Then Lemma 2.5 gives that Φ(R)=Z(H). Altogether UB(H)Φ(R)=B(H)×Φ(R). But then U is a direct product of cyclic groups of prime power order, i.e. a cyclic batten group, and this is a contradiction.

Next suppose that G is a batten group and that U is a subgroup of G. Then U is a direct product of subgroups of the battens of G whose orders are pairwise coprime. Consequently U is a batten group as well, by the arguments above. □

We remark that sections of battens, or batten groups, are not necessarily batten groups. For example, Q8/Z(Q8) is not a batten group.

Lemma 2.8.

Suppose that K is a batten group and that QK is a q-group.

If Q is not normal in K, then there is a non-nilpotent batten B of K such that B=B(B)Q and NK(Q)=CK(Q).

If QEK, then |K:CK(Q)|{1,4} or this index is a prime number.

Proof.

Since K is a batten group, there is a batten B of K such that QB. Moreover there is a subgroup L of K such that K=L×B. Then LCK(B)CK(Q) (*).

We first suppose that Q is not a normal subgroup of K. Since K is a direct product of battens, it follows that Q is not normal in B. Thus B is neither abelian nor hamiltonian (otherwise all subgroups of B would be normal), and it follows that B is not nilpotent. Now Q is a proper subgroup of B because Q EB. We conclude from Lemma 2.5 that neither QB(B) nor QZ(B), whence B=B(B)Q and therefore NB(Q)=Q=CB(Q). Consequently (*) and Dedekind’s modular law yield that NK(Q)=LNB(Q)=LCB(Q)=CK(Q).

Suppose now that QEK. Using (*) we see that |K:CK(Q)|=|B:CB(Q)|. Hence we may suppose that B is not abelian. If B is not nilpotent, then Z(B) and a Sylow q-subgroup of B centralize Q. Thus Lemma 2.5 yields that |K:CK(Q)|=|B:CB(Q)| equals the prime in π(B){q}. Let BQ8 and suppose that QZ(B). Then Q has order 4 or 8. In the first case |K:CK(Q)|=|B:CB(Q)|=|B:Q|=2 and in the second case |K:CK(Q)|=|B:CB(Q)|=|B:Z(B)|=4, which completes the proof. □

3 L10 and its sublattices

Throughout this article we will use the notation from the next definition whenever we refer to L10 and its sublattices:

Definition 3.1.

The lattice L10 is defined to be isomorphic to L(D8), with notation as indicated in the picture.

Now we define

  1. L5:={E,S,U,A,F},

  2. L6:=L5{T},

  3. L7:=L5{D,C},

  4. L8:=L10{B,V},

  5. M8:=L10{T,V},

  6. L9:=L10{V},

  7. M9:=L10{B},

with the corresponding inclusion relations induced from the lattice L10.

Definition 3.2.

Let L be a lattice. An equivalence relation on L is called a congruence relation if and only if, for all ABCDL such that AB and CD, we have that A,CB,D and ACBD.

Lemma 3.3.

Let be a congruence relation on L9={ABCDEFUTS} as in Definition 3.1 and suppose that is not equality. Then ED.

Proof.

Let be a congruence relation on L9 and suppose that ED.

If X{ABCF}, then ED=ED=XD and therefore EX.

First we assume that X0L9{F} is such that FX0. Then there is some X{ABC} such that X0X, and then X=X0,XF,X=F. We choose Y{T,U} such that XY=E. Then E=XYFY=Y and therefore, if Z{T,U}{Y}, then Z=Z,EZ,Y=F. Now it follows that E=ZDFD=D, which gives a contradiction.

We have seen that E is not congruent to any of the elements A,B,C,D,F. Next we assume that X{S,T,U} is such that EX and we choose Y{A,C} such that XY. Then Y=Y,EY,X=F, which gives another contradiction. We conclude that {E} and {F} are singleton classes with respect to .

If there are X,YL{E,F} such that XY and XYXY=E or X,Y=F, then this implies that X=XXXY=E or X=X,XX,Y=F. As this is impossible, we conclude that such elements XY do not exist.

In particular ABC are pairwise non-congruent and DSTU are also pairwise non-congruent.

We assume that DX{ABC}. Then we choose Y{TU} such that YX, and this gives the contradiction FY,DY,X=F. Hence {D} is a singleton as well.

Finally, we assume that there are X{ABC} and Y{TSU} such that XY. We have seen that XYE and then it follows that YX by the structure of L9. Now D=XDYD=E, which is impossible. In conclusion, for all XYL9, we have that XY if and only if X = Y. This means that is equality. □

In the following lemma we argue similarly to Lemma 2.2 in [Citation8].

Lemma 3.4.

Suppose that nN and that G1,,Gn are normal subgroups of G of pair-wise coprime order such that G=G1××Gn. Then G is L9-free if and only if, for every i{1,,n}, the group Gi is L9-free.

Proof.

Since subgroups of L9-free groups are L9-free we just need to verify the “if” part.

Suppose that G1,…,Gn are L9-free. Then Lemma 1.6.4 of [Citation7] implies that L(G)L(G1)××L(Gn). By induction we may suppose that n = 2. Assume that L={ETSUDABCF} is a sublattice of L(G)L(G1)×L(G2) that is isomorphic to L9 as in Definition 3.1. Then the projections φ1 and φ2 of L into L(G1) and L(G2), respectively, are not injective, because L(G1) and L(G2) are L9-free. Let i{1,2} and define, for all XYL: XiY:φi(X)=φi(Y).

Then i is a congruence relation on L, because φi is a lattice homomorphism, but it is not equality because ϕi is not injective. Then Lemma 3.3 implies that φ1(D)=φ1(E) and φ2(D)=φ2(E), and hence D = E. This is a contradiction. □

Lemma 3.5.

L9={ABCDEFUTD} as in Definition 3.1 is completely characterized by the following:

L9(i) DE.

L9(ii) S,T=S,D=T,D=A and ST=SD=TD=E.

L9(iii) D,U=C and DU=E.

L9(iv) S,U=T,U=F.

L9(v) A,B=B,C=F and AB=AC=BC=D.

Proof.

We first remark that L9 satisfies the relations given in L9 (i) – L9 (v).

Suppose conversely that a lattice L={ABCDEFSTU} satisfies the relations given in L9 (i) – L9 (v). Then we see that EABCDSTUF and DABC as well as STA and UC. If these are the unique inclusions and |L|=9, then LL9.

For all XYL such that XY we have that XY=X and XY=Y. Thus L9 (ii) shows that S, T, and D are pair-wise not subgroups of each other.

Using L9 (iii) we obtain that DU and UD, and L9 (iv) gives that also S, T and U are pair-wise not subgroups of each other. In addition, by L9 (v), we have that A, B and C are pair-wise not subgroups of each other. Together with the fact that STA and UC, this implies that AUCS,T and BSTU. Moreover we have that DABC and STA and UC and AFB and CF. Together with L9 (ii) and L9 (iii), this information yields that AU and CS,T as well as BSTU.

We conclude that there is a lattice homomorphism φ from L9 to L. Hence we obtain a congruence relation on L9 by defining that XY if and only if φ(X)=φ(Y), for all X,YL9.

If φ is not injective, then Lemma 3.3 implies that E = D. This contradicts L9 (i). Consequently φ is injective and LL9. □

The next lemma gives an example of a group that is not L9-free.

Lemma 3.6.

D12 is not L9-free.

Proof.

Let G be isomorphic to D12 and let a,bG be such that o(a) = 6, o(b) = 2 and G=a,b. Then we find a sublattice in L(G) isomorphic to L9 by checking the equations from Lemma 3.5.

We let L:={1,b,a2b,a2,ab,a2,b,a,a2,ab,G} and we define A:=a2,b and C:=a2,ab.

L9(i)We see that a21 and hence a1.

L9(ii)We notice that AG is isomorphic to Sym3 with cyclic normal subgroup a2 of order 3 and distinct subgroups ba2b of order 2. Then b,a2b=b,a2=a2b,a2=A and ba2b=ba2=a2ba2=1.

L9(iii)The subgroup C is also isomorphic to Sym3, the subgroup abC has order 2, and moreover a2,ab=C and a2ab=1.

L9(iv)We first see that b,ab=a,b=G and then a2b,ab=a2b(ab)1,ab=a,b=G.

L9(v) a is a cyclic normal subgroup of G of order 6, and the subgroups A and C also have order 6. These three subgroups are maximal in G. Hence A,a=C,a=G. Assume for a contradiction that A = C. Then bC={1,a2,a4,ab,a3b,a5b}, which is false. Since a2 is the unique subgroup of order 3 of G, we conclude that Aa=AC=aC=a2.

Altogether it follows, with Lemma 3.5, that L is isomorphic to L9, and then G is not L9-free. □

The next lemma shows how we can construct an entire class of groups that are not L9-free.

Lemma 3.7.

Suppose that pq and that G = PQ, where P is an elementary abelian normal Sylow p-subgroup of G and Q is a cyclic Sylow q-subgroup of G. Suppose that Q acts irreducibly on [P,Q]1 and that |CP(Q)|3. Then G is not L9-free.

Proof.

Since Q is abelian, we see that E:=CQ(P)EG. We claim that G/CQ(P) is not L9-free. Therefore we may suppose that E = 1.

Our hypotheses imply that [P,Q] is not centralized by Q, and in particular |[P,Q]|3. Moreover |CP(Q)|3 by hypothesis. Since P is elementary abelian, Lemma 1.1 gives that P=[P,Q]×CP(Q).

We let V[P,Q] and DCP(Q) be subgroups of minimal order such that |V|3 and |D|3 and we set A:=V×D. If p is odd, then A has order p2, and if p = 2, then |A|=24=16. In the first case A has p21p1=p+14 subgroups isomorphic to V. In the second case A has 15·143=70 subgroups isomorphic to V, where 3·1422=19 of these subgroups intersect V non-trivially and 19 of them intersect D non-trivially. In both cases, we find subgroups T and S of A isomorphic to V such that |{D,T,S,V}|=4 and TV=TD=TS=SD=SV=1=E.

We recall that A is elementary abelian, and then it follows that L9 (i) and L9 (ii) hold and that A=S,V=T,V (*).

We further set U:=Q. Then UDQP=E=1 and U,D=UD=:C, which implies L9 (iii).

If X{T,S}, then XCP(Q) and then the irreducible action of Q on [P,Q] and Lemma 1.2 yield that V[P,Q]X,U. Using (*) it follows that DAV,X,U=X,U. Combining all this information gives that X,U=[P,Q]DQ. Now if we set F:=[P,Q]DQ, then we have L9 (iv).

To prove our claim, it remains to show that property L9 (v) of Lemma 3.5 is satisfied.

We set B:=DQx for some x[P,Q]#.

If y{1x}, then DADQy=D(AQy)=D and hence AB=AC=D. We further have that DBC=D(QDQx)=DCQ(x)=D, by Lemma 1.4 (b) and (c), because Q acts irreducibly on [P,Q].

In addition, the irreducible action of Qx on [P,Q] and Lemma 1.2 yield that [P,Q]A,Qx. It follows that A,B=[P,Q]DQx=F. Finally we deduce from Part (d) of Lemma 1.4 that B,C=DQ,Qx=D[x,Q]QxQx=D[P,Q]Qx=F.

4 Group orders with few prime divisors

Much of our analysis will focus on non-nilpotent groups with a small number of primes dividing their orders. The next lemma sheds some light on why this situation naturally occurs.

Lemma 4.1.

Suppose that G is L9-free. Then G possesses a normal Sylow subgroup.

Proof.

Assume that this is false. Since G is L9-free and hence L10-free, [Citation9, Corollary C] is applicable. Then G is metacyclic because it does not have any normal Sylow subgroup, and it follows that G is supersoluble. Then Satz VI.9.1(c) in [Citation3] gives a contradiction. □

Lemma 4.2.

Suppose that G is a p-group. Then the following statements are equivalent:

  • L(G) is modular.

  • G is L5-free.

  • G is L9-free.

  • G is L10-free.

Proof.

This lemma follows from Theorem 2.1.2 in [Citation7] and Lemma 2.1 in [Citation9], since L9 is a sublattice of L10 containing L5. □

Lemma 4.3.

Suppose that pq and that G is an L9-free {p, q}-group. Let P be a normal Sylow p-subgroup of G and let QSylq(G). If G is not nilpotent, then Q is cyclic or QQ8.

Proof.

First we note that all subgroups and sections of G are L9-free and that G is L10-free.

Let G be non-nilpotent and assume for a contradiction that Q is neither cyclic nor isomorphic to Q8. Given that G is L10-free, we may apply Theorem B of [Citation9] and we see that neither (a), (b) nor (c) hold. Therefore p = 3 and q = 2. Now there are a,bQ such that a,b is not cyclic and b is an involution. If, for all choices of b, we have that CP(b)=CP(Q), then Ω1(Q) acts element-wise fixed-point-freely on P/CP(Q), contradicting 8.3.4 (b) of [Citation5]. Therefore we may choose b such that a does not centralize CP(b), and we also choose a of minimal order under these constraints. Then a2 centralizes P and a inverts an element xCP(b) by a result of Baer (e.g. 6.7.7 of [Citation5]). If follows that a inverts Ω1(x) and we may suppose that x has order 3. Now x,a,b/Ca(x) is isomorphic to D12, contrary to Lemma 3.6. □

Lemma 4.4.

Suppose that pq and that G is an L9-free {p, q}-group. Furthermore, let P be a normal Sylow p-subgroup of G and let QSylq(G) be cyclic such that 1[P,Q] is elementary abelian.

Then every subgroup of Q acts irreducibly or by inducing (possibly trivial) power automorphism on [P,Q]. Moreover, CP(Q) is a cyclic 2-group and P is abelian.

Proof.

First we note that all subgroups and sections of G are L9-free and that all subgroups and sections of [P,Q] are elementary abelian, by hypothesis. In addition Lemma 2.2 of [Citation9] yields that P=CP(Q)×[P,Q], as G is also L10-free. In particular P is abelian if CP(Q) is.

Assume that the lemma is false and let G be a minimal counterexample.

Since [P,Q] is elementary abelian, we introduce the following notation with Maschke’s theorem:

Let nN and let M1,,Mn[P,Q] be Q-invariant and such that [P,Q]=M1××Mn and that Q acts irreducibly on M1,,Mn, respectively. Lemmas 2.3.5 of [Citation7] and 4.2 yield that Ω1(CP(Q)) is elementary abelian. Now there are rN and cyclic subgroups Mn+1,,Mn+r of Ω1(CP(Q)) such that Ω1(CP(Q))=Mn+1××Mn+r.

We set H1:=(M1××Mn+r1)Q and H2:=(M2××Mn+r)Q.

Then for every i{1,2} the group Op(Hi) is elementary abelian. Moreover Hi is a proper subgroup of G and then the minimal choice of G implies that every subgroup of Q either induces (possibly trivial) power automorphisms on [Op(Hi),Q] or acts irreducibly on it.

(1) CP(Q)=1 and n2.

Proof. We assume for a contradiction that n+r3.

Then Q does not act irreducibly on both Op(H1) and Op(H2), and it follows that Q induces (possibly trivial) power automorphisms on [Op(Hi),Q].

We suppose first that CP(Q)=1. Then [Op(Hi),Q]=Op(Hi) for both i{1,2}. Therefore Lemma 1.5.4 of [Citation7], together with the fact that 1M2Op(H1)Op(H2), provides some kN such that ay=ak for every aOp(H1)Op(H2)=[P,Q]Ω1(CP(Q)). But this means that Q, and hence every subgroup of Q, induces (possibly trivial) power automorphism on Op(H1)Op(H2)=[P,Q] in this case. Thus G is not a counterexample, which is a contradiction.

We conclude that CP(Q)1 and now there is some i{1,2} such that 1[Op(Hi),Q] and COp(Hi)(Q)1. Then Hi satisfies the hypotheses of our lemma and it follows that COp(Hi)(Q) is an non-trivial 2-group. In particular p = 2. But then Lemma 1.3 provides the contradiction that [Op(Hi),Q]=1.

For the proof of (1), we assume for a further contradiction that r=n=1. Then Q acts irreducibly on the elementary abelian group [P,Q] and Lemma 3.7, applied to ([P,Q]×Ω1(CP(Q)))Q, gives that |Ω1(CP(Q))|=2. In particular we have that p = 2. Thus the minimal choice of G and Lemma 1.3 yield, for every proper subgroup U of Q, that U centralizes P or acts irreducibly on [P,Q]=[P,U].

Since G is a counterexample, it follows that CP(Q) is not cyclic. But |Ω1(CP(Q))|=2 and therefore CP(Q) is a generalized quaternion group. It follows that CP(Q)Q8 by Lemma 4.2. In this case 1Z:=Z(CP(Q))EG and G/Z satisfies the hypotheses of our lemma, but not the conclusion. Thus G is not a minimal counterexample, contrary to our choice. □

(2) Q acts irreducibly on P=[P,Q].

Proof. Assume for a contradiction that n = 2. By hypothesis Q is cyclic, and then we may suppose that CQ(M1)CQ(M2)=:Q0. If CQ(M1)=CQ(M2), then Lemma 2.8 of [Citation9] implies that Q induces power automorphisms on P. Thus G is not a counterexample, which is a contradiction.

Therefore CQ(M1)Q0 and 1[M1,Q0][P,Q0]. The minimal choice of G yields that Q0 acts irreducibly or by inducing power automorphisms on [P,Q0] and that CP(Q0) is a cyclic 2-group. Now we notice that M2CP(Q0), but M21=CP(Q), whence we deduce a contradiction from 2.2.5 of [Citation5]. □

Since G = PQ is a counterexample to the lemma, Q has a proper subgroup U that does not act irreducibly on [P,Q]=P and it also does not induce power automorphisms on [P,Q]. In particular it does not act trivially. Since PU is a proper subgroup of our minimal counterexample G, it follows that 1CP(U)P. But CP(U) is Q-invariant, because Q is abelian. This is a final contradiction with regard to (2). □

Lemma 4.5.

Suppose that q is odd and that G is an L9-free {2,q}-group. Suppose further that P is a normal Sylow 2-subgroup of G such that [P,Q] is hamiltonian and let QSylq(G). Then one of the following holds:

  1. G is nilpotent or

  2. [P,Q]Q8 and there exists a group I of order at most 2 such that P=[P,Q]×I and Q is a cyclic 3-group. Moreover [P,Q]Q/Z([P,Q]Q)Alt4.

Proof.

We suppose that G is not nilpotent.

Then Q is not normal in G and Lemma 4.3 implies that Q is cyclic. Furthermore, P is L9-free and hence it is modular by Lemma 4.2. Since [P,Q] is hamiltonian, Theorem 2.3.1 of [Citation7] provides subgroups P0,IP such that P0Q8, I is elementary abelian and P=P0×I.

We recall that the automorphism group of Q8 is isomorphic to Sym4. Thus, if Q8P1P is Q-invariant, but not centralized by Q, then Q8P1[P,Q] and 1|Q/CQ(P1)|=3. It follows that Q is a cyclic 3-group and [P1,Q]Q/Z([P1,Q]Q)Alt4.

We conclude that our assertion holds if I = 1. Now suppose that I1. We recall that P EG and therefore Φ(P0)=Φ(P)G. Since |Φ(P0)|=2, it follows that Φ(P0)Z(G), and then G¯:=G/Φ(P0) is not nilpotent because G is not. Furthermore, G¯ is L9-free, I¯I1Q¯Q and P¯0 is elementary abelian of order 4. In particular P¯ is elementary abelian, hence it is a non-hamiltonian 2-group of order at least 8. Lemma 4.4 states that Q¯ acts irreducibly on [P¯,Q¯]1 or induces power automorphisms on it. The second case is not possible by Lemma 1.3.

Hence QQ¯ acts irreducibly on [P¯,Q¯]=[P,Q]¯ and, by Lemma 4.4, we see that CP¯(Q¯) is a cyclic 2-group. Since I1 and Ω1(P)=Φ(P0)×I, we have that 1I¯=Ω1(P)¯ is Q¯-invariant and P¯0 is a non-cyclic complement of I¯ in P¯. This implies that I¯=CP¯(Q¯) is cyclic and elementary abelian at the same time. Thus II¯ has order 2 and with Lemma 1.1 we deduce that CP(Q)Φ(P0)=IΦ(P0)=Ω1(P) is elementary abelian of order 4. Then we deduce that CP(Q)=Ω1(P) and then [P,Q]CP(Q)1. Moreover, since [P,Q]CP(Q)=P=P1×IP1CQ(P), it follows that |[P,Q]||P1|8. In conclusion, [P,Q] is a subgroup of order at most 8 admitting an automorphism of odd order that centralizes Ω1([P,Q]). It follows that [P,Q]Q8 and then, together with the fact that IZ(G), our assertions follow. □

Definition 4.6.

Suppose that Q is a cyclic q-group that acts coprimely on the p-group P. We say that the action of Q on P avoids L9 (and we indicate more technical details by writing “of type ( ·)”) if and only if one of the following is true:

(std)Every subgroup of Q acts irreducibly or by inducing (possibly trivial) power automorphisms on the elementary abelian group [P,Q]=P.

(cent)Every subgroup of Q acts irreducibly or trivially on the elementary abelian group [P,Q], P is abelian and CP(Q) is a nontrivial cyclic 2-group.

(hamil) [P,Q]Q8P=[P,Q]×I, where I is a group of order at most 2, and Q is a cyclic 3-group such that [P,Q]Q/Z([P,Q]Q)Alt4.

Lemma 4.7.

Suppose that p is an odd prime and that G is an L9-free {2,p}-group. Let further P be a normal Sylow p-subgroup of G and let QSyl2(G) be isomorphic to Q8 and such that 1[P,Q] is elementary abelian.

Then p3mod 4|P|=p2 and Q acts faithfully on P.

Proof.

We set Z:=Ω1(Q). If ZG, then ZZ(G) and we consider G¯:=G/Z. Then G¯ is an L9-free {2,p}-group, P¯ is a normal Sylow p-subgroup of G¯ and Q¯Syl2(G¯). Since Q¯ is neither cyclic nor isomorphic to Q8, Lemma 4.3 is applicable and we see that G¯ is nilpotent. But then G is also nilpotent, contrary to our hypothesis that [P,Q]1. Thus Ω1(Q) is not normal in G and Q acts faithfully on P. Now, for all yQ of order 4, we apply Lemma 4.4 on [P,Q]y to deduce that y either induces power automorphisms on [P,Q] or acts irreducibly on it. Theorem 1.5.1 of [Citation7] states that PotG(P) is abelian, but QQ8 is not, which means that we may choose y such that y does not induce power automorphisms on P. In particular P is not cyclic of prime order. Moreover p is odd and therefore 4 divides (p+1)(p1)=p21, and Satz II 3.10 of [Citation3] yields that |P|p2. It follows that |P|=p2. More precisely, as |P|p, the result implies that p3(mod4), and then the proof is complete. □

Definition 4.8.

Suppose that QQ8 acts coprimely on the p-group P. We say that the action of Q on P avoids L9 if and only if p3mod 4|P|=p2 and Q acts faithfully on P.

Lemma 4.9.

Suppose QQ8 and that P is a p-group on which Q acts avoiding L9. Then P is elementary abelian, Ω1(Q) inverts P, and every subgroup of Q of order at least 4 acts irreducibly on P.

Proof.

Since a cyclic group of order p2 has an abelian automorphism group by 2.2.3 of [Citation5], it follows that P is elementary abelian. If 1R is a cyclic subgroup of P, then |Aut(R)|=p1 and therefore R does not admit an automorphism of order 4. Additionally, [P,Ω1(Q)] is Q-invariant and, since Q acts faithfully on P, we see that [P,Ω1(Q)]1. Furthermore, Lemma 1.1 gives that [P,Ω1(Q)]CP(Ω1(Q))=1 because P is abelian. Moreover, Q has rank 1, and then it follows that Q acts faithfully on [P,Ω1(Q)]. This implies that |[P,Ω1(Q)]|p and consequently [P,Ω1(Q)]=P. Hence 8.1.8 of [Citation5] states that Ω1(Q) inverts P. In particular Ω1(Q) inverts every cyclic subgroup R of P.

In addition, these arguments show that every subgroup U of order 4 of Q does not normalize any nontrivial proper subgroup of the elementary abelian group P. This means that U acts irreducibly on P. □

Corollary 4.10.

Suppose that pq and that G is an L9-free {p, q}-group such that PSylp(G) is normal in G and QSylq(G).

Then either G is nilpotent and P and Q are modular or Q is a batten and it acts on P avoiding L9.

In particular, if G is not nilpotent, then Q is isomorphic to Q8 or cyclic and [P,Q] is elementary abelian or isomorphic to Q8, where in the second case q = 3.

Proof.

By hypothesis G is L9-free, hence P and Q are, too. Then Lemma 4.2 implies that P and Q are modular.

Suppose that G is not nilpotent. Then Lemma 4.3 applies: Q is cyclic or isomorphic to Q8 and hence it is a batten. Moreover Lemma 2.2 of [Citation9] states that [P,Q] is a hamiltonian 2-group or elementary abelian. In the first case Lemma 4.5 gives the assertion. In the second case our statement follows from Lemmas 4.4 and 4.7. □

Lemma 4.11.

Let Q be a nilpotent batten that acts on the p-group P avoiding L9, and suppose that U is a subgroup of Q.

Then U induces power automorphisms on P or it acts irreducibly on [P,Q]/Φ([P,Q]).

Proof.

First suppose that QQ8. Then Lemma 4.9 implies that every subgroup of order at least 4 of Q, and in particular Q itself, acts irreducibly on P=[P,Q]/Φ([P,Q]). Moreover, the involution of Q inverts P by Lemma 4.9, and then the statement holds.

Next we suppose that Q is cyclic. Then Definition 4.6 gives the assertion unless the action of Q on P avoids L9 of type (hamil). In this case every proper subgroup of Q centralizes P, while Q acts irreducibly on [P,Q]/Z([P,Q])=[P,Q]/Φ([P,Q]). □

Next we investigate groups of order divisible by more than two primes. This needs some preparation.

Lemma 4.12.

Suppose that P and R are distinct Sylow subgroups of G, that QSylq(G) is cyclic and that it normalizes P and R, but does not centralize them. Suppose further that R normalizes every Q-invariant subgroup of P. If CQ(P)=CQ(R), then G is not L9-free.

Proof.

We suppose that CQ(P)=CQ(R)=:E. Then E is a normal subgroup of G because Q is abelian.

We claim that G/E is not L9-free, and for this we may suppose that E = 1. Then Q1 acts faithfully on P and R. Now we need a technical step before we move on:

There are a Q-invariant subgroup D of P and elements x,yD such that CQ(x)=CQ(y)=CQ(xy1)=1 and D=[x,Q]=[y,Q]=[xy1,Q]. (*)

Since Q is cyclic, there is some uQ such that u=Q. Let x0[P,Q] be such that Ω1(Q) does not centralize x0.

Then [x0,Q]=[x0,u,Q]=[[x0,u],Q]=[[x0,u],Q] by Lemma 1.1, and for all integers n we have the following: (x01x0u)un=1 iff (HTML translation failed) iff x0u=1. It follows that [x0,u][[x0,u],Q]=[x,Q] and CQ([x0,u])=CQ(x0)=1.

Now we set x:=[x0,u]y:=xu and D:=[x,Q]. Then D is Q-invariant and we have that x,yDCQ(x)=CQ(y)=1 and D=[x,Q]=[y,Q]. If we set z:=xy1, then z=[x1,u] and we can use the information from the end of the previous paragraph:

[z,Q]=[x1,Q]=D and CQ(z)=CQ(x1)=CQ(x)=1. This concludes the proof of (*).

We use (*) and its notation and, similarly, we find a Q-invariant subgroup R0 of R and an element hR0 such that CQ(h)=1 and R0=[h,Q].

We set S:=QxT=Qy, A:=DQB:=DR0U:=QhC:=DQh and F:=DR0Q, and we claim that {ABCDEFSTU} is isomorphic to L9. The properties L9 (i) and L9 (iii) of Lemma 3.5 follow from the choice of D, since h and Q normalize D.

For L9 (ii) we first note that DQx=DQy=1=E and D,Qx=D,Qy=DQ, since xD and hence y=xuD. Next, Lemma 1.4 (b) yields that TS=QxQyCQ(xy1)y=1. Part (d) of the same lemma shows that T,S=Qx,Qy=[xy1,Q]Qxy1Qxy1=DQxy1=DQ=A, as xy1D.

For all z{x,y} we calculate that Qz,Qh=[zh1,Q]Qzh1Qzh1= ([z,Q]h1[h1,Q])Qzh1Qzh1 =D,R0Qzh1=F by Lemma 1.4 (d). Thus L9 (iv) of Lemma 3.5 is true.

We moreover have that A,B=D,Q,R0=F=D,Qh,R0 and AB=DQDR0=D(QDR0)=D=D(QhDR0)=CB. Finally AC=DQDQh=D(QDQh)DCQ(h)=D by Lemma 1.4 (b).

Using Lemma 3.5 we conclude that G/E is not L9-free, and hence G is not L9-free. □

Corollary 4.13.

Suppose that p,q and r are pairwise distinct primes and that G is a directly indecomposable L9-free {p, q, r}-group. Suppose further that PSylp(G) and RSylr(G) are normal in G and let QSylq(G).

Then Q is cyclic and CQ(P)CQ(R).

Proof.

Since G is directly indecomposable, we see that Q acts non-trivially on both P and R. Moreover, PQ and RQ are L9-free by hypothesis, and then we conclude that Q is cyclic or isomorphic to Q8.

In the first case, our assertion follows from Lemma 4.12, and in the second case, we choose a maximal subgroup Q1 of Q. Then Q1 acts irreducibly on P and R by Lemma 4.9, and the same Lemma shows that Φ(Q) inverts P and R. Thus Q1 acts on P and on R avoiding L9, respectively, and it acts faithfully. This contradicts Lemma 4.12. □

We explain another example where a subgroup lattice contains L9.

Lemma 4.14.

Suppose that p, q and r are pairwise distinct primes and that G is a {p, q, r}-group. Suppose further that PSylp(G) is normal in G and that QSylq(G) and RSylr(G) are cyclic groups such that RERQ. Suppose that |R|=r and CQ(R)=1.

If R acts irreducibly on P, but non-trivially, and if 1[P,Q] is elementary abelian, then G is not L9-free.

Proof.

We first remark that G is soluble, because PEPREPRQ=G. We will construct the lattice L9 in L(G) using Lemma 3.5. For this we set E:=1 and D:=P. Then DE and we see that L9 (i) is true.

Next, we recall that 1[P,Q] by hypothesis. Assume that |[P,Q]|=2. Then Q, which normalizes [P,Q], must centralize it, and then Lemma 1.1 gives a contradiction.

Therefore |[P,Q]|2. As a consequence, we find a,b[P,Q]# such that ab, and then we set S:=Ra and T:=Rb. Now DS=1=E=DT and D,T=PRb=PR=PRa=D,S. We set A:=PR. In addition, since R acts irreducibly, but non-trivially on P, it follows that CR(ba1)R. Then the fact that |R|=r gives that CR(ba1)=1=E.

Lemma 1.4 (b) shows that ST=(RRba1)aCR(ba1)a=E, and now we recall that [ba1,R]1. Moreover, R acts irreducibly on P, and then Part (e) of the same lemma yields the following:

T,S=R,Rba1a=([ba1,R]Rba1Rba1)a=PR=A. We conclude that L9 (ii) holds.

For L9 (iii) we set U:=Q and C:=D,Q=PQ. Then we note that UD=QP=1=E.

Assume for a contradiction that X:=Rc,Q has odd order for some c{a,b}.

In both cases X is a p-Hall subgroup of the soluble group G = PRQ and therefore Rc=Or(X). It follows that Q normalizes Rc and then that Qc1 and Q normalize R.

Since NP(R) is R-invariant and R acts irreducibly, but non-trivially on P, we conclude that NG(R)=RQ. Thus Sylow’s theorem provides some yR such that Qc1=Qy. Now [yc,Q]PRQ=1. In addition |R|=r and [R,Q]1 by hypothesis. Together this gives that ycCG(Q)PRPQPR=P(QPR)=P, by Dedekind’s modular law. Altogether we have that ycCP(Q). We recall that c{a,b}P, and then y=ycc1P. But we chose yR and now yRP=1, whence Qc1=Q. In other words, cNP(Q), and this means that [Q,c]QP=1 and cCP(Q). We recall that c[P,Q]# and that [P,Q] is elementary abelian by hypothesis. Then Lemma 1.1 implies that [P,Q]=[P,Q,Q]×C[P,Q](Q), and this contradicts the fact that cCP(Q)[P,Q].

It follows that X has even order and since Rc acts irreducibly on P, we conclude that PX. This implies that S,U=Ra,Q=PRQ=G=Rb,Q=T,Q and then L9 (iv) holds for F:=G.

We finally set B:=PQz for some zR#. Then R=z and Lemma 1.4 (b) and (c), together with our hypothesis, show that PPQPQz=P(QPQz)PCQ(z)=PCQ(R)=P. Thus we have that BC=P=D. We further see that AC=PRPQ=P(RPQ)=P=D and AB=PRPQz=P(RPQz)=P=D. Since A,B=PR,PQz=PQR=G and B,C=PQ,PQz=P[Q,z]QzQz=P[Q,R]Q=PRQ=G by Lemma 1.4 (d), we finally obtain L9 (v).

Altogether Lemma 3.5 gives the assertion. □

Proposition 4.15.

Suppose that p,q, and r are pairwise distinct primes and that G is a non-nilpotent L9-free {p, q, r}-group with normal Sylow p-subgroup P. Suppose further that RSylr(G) and QSylq(G) are not normal in G, that RERQ and [R,Q]1.

Then RQ is a batten, P is elementary abelian of order pr, R and Q act irreducibly on P and Φ(Q) induces non-trivial power automorphisms on P.

Proof.

We proceed in a series of steps.

(1) The groups PQ and PR are not nilpotent, Q is cyclic and RQ8 or |R|=r. In addition R=[R,Q] and [R,CQ(P)]CR(P).

Proof. By hypothesis R is not normal in G, but Q normalizes R. Hence PNG(R) and in particular PR is not nilpotent. But PR is L9-free, because G is. Moreover, RQ is non-nilpotent and L9-free, again by hypothesis. Then Corollary 4.10 implies that R and Q are battens, that R acts on P avoiding L9 and that Q acts on R avoiding L9. More specifically, R and Q are cyclic or isomorphic to Q8, and [P,R] as well as [R,Q] are elementary abelian or isomorphic to Q8.

It follows that RQ8 or that R is cyclic of order r. In both cases Lemma 1.1 yields R=[R,Q] and the avoiding L9 action of Q on R gives that Q is cyclic.

In addition [P,CQ(P),R]=1[P,R,CQ(P)][P,CQ(P)]=1 and then the Three Subgroups Lemma (see for example 1.5.6 of [Citation5]) implies that 1=[R,CQ(P),P]. Thus [R,CQ(P)]CR(P).

If it was true that [P,Q]=1, then R=[R,Q]=[R,CQ(P)] would centralize P. But this is a contradiction. □

(2) CR(P)=1 and CQ(P)Z(G).

Proof. Since [P,R]1 by (1), we can apply Corollary 4.10 to PR, and this shows that R acts on P avoiding L9. Otherwise (1) implies that RQ8 and then Definition 4.8 gives that R acts faithfully on P. If |R|=r, then R acts faithfully of P because [P,R]1. In both cases we see that CR(P)=1, and then the last statement of (1) implies that [R,CQ(P)]CR(P)=1. Then CQ(P) centralizes P and R, and Q is cyclic by (1), and therefore it follows that CQ(P)Z(G). □

(3) Z(G) = 1 or p2.

Proof. We suppose that p = 2. Let :GG/Z(G) be the natural homomorphism. We show that G¯ satisfies the hypotheses of our lemma.

From (1) we see that none of the groups P, Q or R is contained in Z(G). We even have that RZ(G)=1 by (1). In particular p,q,rπ(G¯) and G¯ is L9-free. We see that P¯ is a normal Sylow p-subgroup of G and that Q¯Sylq(G) and R¯Sylr(G) are such that R¯ER¯Q¯G. Let X{R,Q}. If X¯EG¯, then XZ(G)EG and X is a characteristic Sylow subgroup of XZ(G) and hence normal in G. This is a contradiction.

We deduce that all hypotheses of the lemma hold for G¯ and that [R¯,Q¯]=[R,Q]¯=R¯1. Therefore, if Z(G)1, then the minimal choice of G implies that Φ(Q¯) induces non-trivial power automorphisms on the elementary abelian group P¯. Then Lemma 1.3 yields that p2. □

(4) CP(R)=1, and the groups [P,Q] and P=[P,R] are elementary abelian.

Proof. As PR and PQ are not nilpotent by (1), Corollary 4.10 implies that X acts on P avoiding L9 and that [P,X] is elementary abelian or isomorphic to Q8 for both X{Q,R}.

Assume for a contradiction that [P,X] is isomorphic to Q8 for some X{Q,R}. Then X acts on P of type (hamil). Hence we obtain a group I of order 1 or 2 such that PQ8×I. It follows that Aut(P) is a {2, 3}-group. But this is impossible because Q and R both act coprimely and non-trivially on P by (1), and p = 2, q and r are pairwise distinct.

We conclude that [P,Q] and [P,R] are elementary abelian, and then it follows that P is abelian, by Lemma 4.4, applied to PR.

Assume for a further contradiction that CP(R)1. As R avoids L9 in its action on P, it follows from Lemma 4.9 that R is not isomorphic to Q8. Now (1) yields that R is cyclic and we may apply Lemma 4.4 to PR, because [P,R] is elementary abelian. It follows that CP(R) is a cyclic 2-group and thus q and r are odd.

Furthermore CP(R) is normalized by Q, because Q normalizes P and R. Since q is odd, it follows that CP(R) is centralized by Q. We recall that P is abelian, and then (3) yields that CP(R)Z(G)=1. This is a contradiction.

Altogether CP(R)=1 and Lemma 1.1 gives that P=[P,R] is elementary abelian. □

(5) CP(Q)=1 and Q acts on P avoiding L9 of type (std).

Proof. Since PQ is not nilpotent and Q is cyclic by (1), Corollary 4.10 implies that the action of Q on P avoids L9. But P is elementary abelian by (4), and therefore the action is not of type (hamil).

We assume for a contradiction that CP(Q)1. Then it follows that PQ is not of type (std). We consequently have type (cent) and we see that CP(Q) is a cyclic 2-group. In particular p = 2, and thus q and r are odd. Then |R|=r by (1).

Next we claim that G satisfies the hypotheses of Lemma 4.14.

First, q and r are pairwise distinct odd primes and G is a finite {2,q,r}-group. From above, (1) and our assumption we see that PSyl2(G) is normal in G and that QSylq(G) and RSylr(G) are cyclic groups such that RERQ. We have shown that R has order r.

We recall that CP(Q) is a cyclic 2-group (first paragraph). As r is odd and CP(R)=1 by (4), we see that CP(Q) is not R-invariant. But CP(CQ(R)) is R-invariant, and now the irreducible action of R on P and the fact that 1CP(Q)CP(CQ(R)) show that P=CP(CQ(R)). Then (2) and (4) imply that CQ(R)CQ(P)Z(G)=1.

By (4) P is an elementary abelian 2-group, and P=[P,R]1 by (1) and (4). In particular R does not induce power automorphism on P by Lemma 1.3. As CP(R)=1 by (4), we deduce that R acts irreducibly on P (using Lemma 4.4). Finally, (1) and (4) yield that 1[P,Q] is elementary abelian.

All hypotheses of Lemma 4.14 are satisfied now, and we infer that G is not L9-free. This is a contradiction.

Thus CP(Q)=1 and we deduce that the action of Q on P is not of type (cen). It remains that Q acts on P avoiding L9 of type (std). □

(6) R and Q act irreducibly on P. If XQ induces power automorphisms on P, then X centralizes R.

Proof. We recall from (2) that CQ(P)Z(G) and CR(P)=1. Consequently CRQ(P)=CQ(P)Z(RQ) and RQ/CQ(P) is isomorphic to a subgroup of Out(P). Since RQ is not nilpotent, we see that RQ/CQ(P) is not nilpotent.

The group P is an elementary abelian p-group by (4) and hence, if XRQ induces power automorphisms on it, then it follows that XCQ(P)/CQ(P)Z(RQ/CQ(P)), see page 177 of [Citation3]. We denote this fact by (*). Then we deduce that [R,X]CQ(P)Z(RQ) (see above) and therefore [R,X]=[X,R]=[X,R,R]=1 by Lemma 1.1.

In addition, the fact (*) shows that neither R nor Q induces power automorphisms on P. It follows from (5) and Definition 4.6 (std) that Q acts irreducibly on P. Furthermore (1), together with Corollary 4.10, yields that R acts on P avoiding L9. Since CP(R)=1 by (4), this action has type (std) or (hamil). In the first case, the irreducible action follows from Definition 4.6 (std), and in the second case, it follows from Lemma 4.9. □

(7) CQ(R) induces nontrivial power automorphisms on P.

Proof. We set Q0:=CQ(R) and we assume that Q0 acts irreducibly on P. Then II 3.11 of [Citation3] implies that RQ=CRQ(Q0) is isomorphic to a subgroup of the multiplicative group of some field of order |P|, and it follows that RQ is cyclic. This is a contradiction.

Thus (6) and Lemma 4.11 show that Q0 induces power automorphisms on P. Since R normalizes every Q-invariant subgroup of P by (7), we see from Lemma 4.12 and (2) that CQ(R)CQ(P). □

(8) |P|=pq and Φ(Q)=CQ(R).

Proof. We recall that Q is cyclic, by (1). Moreover [R,Q]1, whence CQ(R)<Q and therefore we may choose yQ such that CQ(R)<y.

By (5) and Lemma 4.11, it follows that every subgroup of y either acts irreducibly on P or induces power automorphism on it (in particular normalizing every subgroup of P). Then Py satisfies (b) of Lemma 3.1 in [Citation8], which implies that it satisfies one of the possibilities 3.1 (i)–3.1 (iii). By (5) and the choice of y, we see that 3.1 (i) is not true. Further (7) provides some xCQ(R) that induces a power automorphism of order q on P. This implies that q divides p – 1 and therefore Py satisfies (ii) of Lemma 3.1 (b) in [Citation8]. It follows that |P|=pq and that, if k is the largest positive integer such that qk divides p – 1, then y induces an automorphism of order qk+1 on P. We conclude that qk+1=|y:Cy(P)|=|y:CR(P)|, because Q is cyclic. Finally, we deduce that o(y) is uniquely determined, that Q=y and that CQ(P)=Φ(Q). □

By (6), we see that R and Q act irreducibly on P, and (1) gives that Q is cyclic. Then (8) and (7) say that Φ(Q) induces nontrivial power automorphisms on P. In addition P is elementary abelian by (4), and it has order pr by (8). If |R|=r, then R is a cyclic group of order r and RQ is a batten. In particular G satisfies the assertion of our lemma.

But G is a counterexample, and then it follows that RQ8 and r = 2. Then (4) yields that PR fulfills the hypothesis of Lemma 4.7, and consequently pr=p2=|P|=pq by (8). This is our final contradiction, because qr. □

Definition 4.16.

Suppose that B is a non-nilpotent batten that acts coprimely on the p-group P. We say that the action of B on P avoids L9 if and only if [P,Z(B)]1 and if one of the following occurs:

(Cy) [P,B(B)]=1 and Q acts on P avoiding L9 for every Sylow subgroup Q of B different from B(B) or

(NN)P is elementary abelian of order p|B:B(B)Z(B)| and the Sylow subgroups of B act irreducibly on P, while Z(B) induces power automorphisms on P.

As in Definition 4.6, we specify the type of the L9-avoiding action by writing that B acts on P avoiding L9 of type ( ·)”.

Lemma 4.17.

Let B be a batten that acts non-trivially and avoiding L9 on the p-group P. Then the following hold:

  1. If CP(B)1, then p = 2.

  2. Either P=[P,B]×CP(B), where [P,B] is elementary abelian and CP(B) is cyclic, or P=[P,B]×I, where I is a group of order at most 2 and [P,B]Q8.

  3. CP(B) is centralized by every automorphism of P of order coprime to p that leaves CP(B) invariant.

Proof.

If BQ8, then Definition 4.8 and Lemma 4.9 imply that P is elementary abelian and that B acts irreducibly on it. We conclude that P=[P,B] is elementary abelian and we deduce from Lemma 1.1 that CP(B)=1. Hence, in this case, all statements of our lemma hold.

Now suppose that B is not nilpotent and that it acts of type (NN). Then Definition 4.16 states that, once more, P is elementary abelian and B acts irreducibly on it. Again we see that P=[P,B] is elementary abelian, and as before all statements hold.

Next we suppose B is not nilpotent and that it acts of type (Cy), or that B is cyclic. In the first case B has a cyclic Sylow subgroup Q that acts on P avoiding L9 such that CP(Q)=CP(B) and [P,B]=[P,Q] by Definition 4.16. In the second case we set Q:=B.

Then, in both cases, Q is a cyclic group that acts on P avoiding L9 such that CP(Q)=CP(B) and [P,B]=[P,Q]. If Q acts of type (std), then P=[P,Q] is elementary abelian by Definition 4.6. Again we deduce the statements of our lemma.

Suppose that Q acts of type (cent). Then Definition 4.6 yields that [P,Q]=[P,B] is elementary abelian, that P is abelian and that CP(Q)=CP(B) is a cyclic 2-group. In particular P=[P,B]×CP(B) by Lemma 1.1. It also follows that CP(B) is centralized by every automorphisms of P of odd order that leaves CP(B) invariant. These are the statements of our lemma.

Finally, suppose that Q acts of type (hamil). Then Definition 4.6 yields that [P,Q]Q8 and P=[P,Q]×I, where I is a group of order at most 2. In particular statement (a) is true. Moreover, we deduce that CP(Q)Ω1(P)=Φ([P,Q])×I, where Φ([P,Q]) is cyclic of order 2. In particular Φ([P,Q]) is centralized by B and by every automorphisms of P. We conclude that CP(Q) is elementary abelian of order at most 4 and that every automorphism of P centralizes a cyclic subgroup of order 2. This implies (b). □

5 Avoiding L9

We now work toward a classification of arbitrary L9-free groups, and therefore we need to understand in more detail the group structures that appear when “L9 is avoided” in the sense of the previous section.

Definition 5.1.

Suppose that K is a batten group that acts coprimely on the p-group P. We say that the action of K on P avoids L9 if and only if [P,K]1 and every batten of K either centralizes P or avoids L9 in its action on P.

Lemma 5.2.

Let K be a batten group that acts coprimely on the p-group P avoiding L9. Suppose further that LK and L0EL such that [P,L]1=[P,L0]. Then L/L0 acts on P avoiding L9. In particular L/L0 is a batten group.

Proof.

By induction we may suppose that K is a batten and that either L0=1 and L is a maximal subgroup of K or that L0 is a minimal normal subgroup of K = L. Thus either |L0| has order q or |K:L|=q. Since L0CK(P), we first remark that L/L0 induces automorphisms on P.

If KQ8, then K acts faithfully on P by Definition 4.8. Thus L0CK(P)=1 and it follows that L is a cyclic group of order 4. Thus Lemma 4.9 yields that Ω1(L) inverts P and that L acts irreducibly on the elementary abelian group P=[P,L]. Then we see that LL/L0 acts on P avoiding L9 of type (std).

Next suppose that K is cyclic. Then L/L0 is cyclic. If K acts of type (std) on P, then L and every subgroup of L act irreducibly or via inducing power automorphisms on the elementary abelian group P=[P,K]. Since [P,L]1 and power automorphisms are universal, by Lemma 1.5.4 of [Citation7], it follows that P=[P,L]. Moreover, the action of L on P is equivalent to that of L/L0, and then it follows that L/L0 acts on P avoiding L9 of type (std).

If K acts on P of type (cent), then L and all its subgroups act irreducibly or trivially on the elementary abelian group [P,K]. Again the fact that [P,L]1 implies that P=[P,L], and then CP(L)=CP(K) by Lemma 1.1. Since the action of L on P is equivalent to that of L/L0, it follows that L/L0 acts on P avoiding L9 of type (cent).

We suppose now that K acts of type (hamil). Then K is a cyclic 3-group and K/CK(P) has order 3. It follows that L = K. But again, the action of L/L0=K/L0 on P is equivalent to the action of K on P, which means that it has type (hamil).

We finally suppose that K is a non-nilpotent batten. Let R be a Sylow subgroup of K such that K=B(K)·R. Suppose first that L/L0 is a q-group. Then our choice of L and L0 implies that L/L0R. If K acts on P of type (Cy) in this case, then it follows that L/L0R is cyclic and that it acts on P avoiding L9, according to Definition 4.16. Otherwise, if K acts of type (NN), then B(K)CK(P) and then L0=1. It follows that L = R acts irreducibly on the elementary abelian group P, whence P=[P,L]=[P,L/L0]. In addition Φ(L) and all of its subgroups induce power automorphism on P. Altogether the cyclic group L/L0L acts on P of type (std).

Now we suppose that L/L0 does not have prime power order. Then L0Φ(R)=Z(K). Now if L/L0 is nilpotent, then LK and therefore L0=1. It follows from Lemma 2.5 that L=Z(K)×B(K). We have already proven that R acts on P avoiding L9, and then Z(K) also acts on P avoiding L9. In addition B(K) either centralizes P or it acts irreducibly on the elementary abelian group P=[P,B(K)]. Since B(K) has prime order, it follows that the cyclic group B(K) acts on P avoiding L9 of type (std). Altogether L/L0L=Z(K)×B(K) acts on P avoiding L9.

Finally, suppose that L/L0 is not nilpotent. Then L is not nilpotent and hence Lemma 2.7 implies that L = K. We conclude that L01. Since [P,Z(K)]1 by Definition 4.16, it follows that L0 is a proper subgroup of Z(K) and that L/L0=K/L0B(K)R/L0 is a non-nilpotent batten. If [P,B(K)]=1, then our investigation above imply that the cyclic group R/L0 acts on P avoiding L9, and then K/L0 acts on P avoiding L9. Otherwise 1[P,B(K)] is elementary abelian of order p|K:B(K)Z(K)|=p|K/L0:B(K)Z(K)/L0|, moreover B(K)B(K)L)/L0 and R/L0 act irreducibly on P. At the same time Z(K/L0)=Z(K)/L0 induces power automorphisms on P. Altogether K/L0 acts on P avoiding L9 of type (NN). □

Lemma 5.3.

Let K be a batten group that acts coprimely on the p-group P avoiding L9. Then the following assertions are true:

  1. If L EK, then [P,K]=[P,L] or [P,L]=1.

  2. [P,K] is elementary abelian or isomorphic to Q8.

Proof.

Let LEK be such that [P,L]1. Then L is a batten group by Lemma 2.7 and therefore there is a batten B of L such that [P,B]1. Assume for a contradiction that [P,B][P,L][P,K]P. Then the fact that P[P,B] implies that CP(B)1 by Lemma 1.1. In addition B avoids L9 in its action on P, by Lemma 5.2. Since B is a batten of L, it is characteristic in L, and therefore B EK. In particular CP(B) is K-invariant and hence it is centralized by K by Lemma 4.17 (c). This implies that CP(B)=CP(K). Finally [P,K]=[[P,B]CP(B),K]=[[P,B]CP(K),K]=[[P,B],K][P,B][P,K], which is a contradiction. In particular (a) is true.

Together with Lemma 4.17 (b), the statement in (b) follows from (a). □

Lemma 5.4.

Let K be a batten group that acts on the p-group P avoiding L9, and suppose that H is a subgroup of K. Then H centralizes P or [P,H]=[P,K].

Moreover, H induces power automorphisms on P or it acts irreducibly on [P,K]/Φ([P,K]).

Proof.

Let HK. If H centralizes P, then it induces power automorphisms on P. We may suppose that [P,H]1. Then H has a q-subgroup Q such that [P,Q]1. Therefore, if QEK, then we have that [P,K]=[P,Q] by Lemma 5.3 (a). Then the fact that [P,Q][P,H][P,K] yields that [P,H]=[P,K].

Assume for a contradiction that [P,K][P,H]. Then Lemma 2.8 implies that K has a non-nilpotent batten B such that B=B(B)Q. We moreover deduce that [P,Q][P,K] and [P,B]=[P,K] by Lemma 5.3 (a), because BEK. Since the action of K on P avoids L9, the action of B also does. If B acts of type (Cy), then we obtain the contradiction that [P,Q]=[P,B]. Thus B acts of type (NN) and in particular Q acts irreducibly on P. But this is impossible as well. It follows that [P,H]=[P,K].

Assume for a further contradiction that HK neither induces power automorphisms on P nor does it act irreducibly on [P,K]/Φ([P,K])=[P,H]/Φ([P,H]). Then there is a batten B of H that neither induces power automorphisms on P nor does it act irreducibly on [P,H]/Φ([P,H]). Similarly to the arguments above, we deduce that [P,K]=[P,H]=[P,B], and Lemma 5.2 gives that B avoids L9 in its action on P. Therefore Lemma 4.11 yields that B is not nilpotent. From Definition 4.16 we further see that B does not act of type (NN), and thus B acts of type (Cy) on P. Consequently [P,B(B)]=1 and B has a cyclic Sylow subgroup Q such that B=B(B)Q and Q acts on P avoiding L9. Again we have [P,K]=[P,B]=[P,Q] and Lemma 4.11 gives that Q induces power automorphisms on P or acts irreducibly on [P,Q]/Φ([P,Q])=[P,K]/Φ([P,K]). In the first case B=CB(P)Q induces power automorphism on P and in the second case B acts irreducibly on [P,K]/Φ([P,K]). This is a contradiction. □

Lemma 5.5.

Let K be a batten group that acts on the p-group P avoiding L9, and suppose that H is a subgroup of K that acts non-trivially on RP.

Then CH(R)=CH(P)CP(H)=CP(K) and [P,H]=[P,K].

Proof.

From Lemma 5.4 we see that [P,H]=[P,K]. In addition CP(K)CP(H)CP(Q) for every q-subgroup Q of H and every prime q. Let Q be a q-subgroup of H for some prime q such that CP(Q)P. Then Q is a batten by Lemma 2.7, and it acts on P avoiding L9 by Lemma 5.2. If Q EK, then K centralizes CP(Q) by Lemma 4.17(c). Thus CP(K)CP(H)CP(Q)CP(K), and this gives that CP(K)=CP(H). If Q is not a normal subgroup of K, then Lemma 2.8 provides a non-nilpotent batten B of K such that B=B(B)Q. Since the action of K on P avoids L9, the action of B also does. If B acts of type (NN), then Q acts irreducibly on P and therefore CP(Q)=1CP(K). Again we deduce that CP(K)=CP(H). If B acts of type (Cy), then [P,B(B)]=1 and hence CP(B)=CP(Q). But now B is a normal subgroup of K, and then Lemma 4.17(c) gives that CP(B)=CP(Q)CP(K). As above we deduce that CP(K)=CP(H).

Finally, suppose that RP is H-invariant, but not centralized by H, and set H0:=CH(R)CH(P). Assume for a contradiction that H0 does not centralize P. Then we deduce, as above, that CP(K)=CP(H0)R. This is a contradiction, because H does not centralize R. □

Corollary 5.6.

Let K be a batten group that acts non-trivially and avoiding L9 on the p-group P. Then the following hold:

  1. If CP(K)1, then p = 2.

  2. If CP(K)=1, then P=[P,K] is elementary abelian.

  3. If K induces power automorphisms on P, then P=[P,K] is elementary abelian of odd order. In particular CP(K)=1 in this case.

Proof.

Let B be a batten of K that does not centralize P. Then Lemma 5.5 implies that CP(K)=CP(B). Thus Part (a) and (b) of Lemma 4.17 yield the statements (a) and (b) of our lemma. For Part (c) we suppose that K induces power automorphisms on P. Then P is not an elementary abelian 2-group by Lemma 1.3. If CP(K)=1, then our assertion holds by (b). Otherwise p = 2 by (a), and then Lemma 1.3 implies that [P,K] is neither elementary abelian nor isomorphic to Q8, contradicting Part (b) of Lemma 5.3.

For the final comment we just use that p is odd and then apply (a). □

Lemma 5.7.

Let B be a batten that acts on the p-group P avoiding L9. Let RP be B-invariant and R0CP(B).

Then B avoids L9 in its action on R/R0.

Proof.

Since B centralizes R0, the action of B on R/R0 is well-defined.

We first suppose that BQ8. Then Lemma 4.9 yields that B acts irreducibly on P, and then it follows that R = P and R0=1. Thus our assertion is true in this case.

Next suppose that B is cyclic. If B acts of type (std) on P, then R0CP(B)=1. If B acts irreducibly on P, then again P = R and there is nothing left to prove. Otherwise B and all of its subgroups induce power automorphisms on P, and hence on R=[R,B] as well. It follows that B also acts of type (std) on RR/R0.

Suppose now that B acts of type (cent). Then, since B does not centralize R and B acts irreducibly on [P,B], it follows that [P,B]R. Moreover P is abelian and then we use the fact that R0CP(B). This gives that R/R0=[R/R0,B]×CR/R0(B)[R,B]×CR(B)/R0, where CR(B)/R0 is a cyclic 2-group. Since every subgroup of B that does not centralize P acts irreducibly on [P,B][R/R0,B] in this case, there are two possibilities for the action of B on RR/R0: If R0CR(B), then B acts of type (cent), and otherwise it acts of type (std).

Suppose now that B acts of type (hamil). Then the cyclic 3-group B acts irreducibly on [P,B]/Φ([P,B]), by Lemma 5.4, and we see again that [P,B]R. It follows that RQ8×I, where I is a group of order at most 2, and then R0CR(B)Φ([R,B])×I. We remark that [R/R0,B]B/Z([R/R0,B]B)[R,B]B/Z([R,B]B)[P,B]B/Z([P,B]B)Alt4.

If R0[P,B]=1, then R/R0Q8×J˜ for some group J of order |I||R0|. Thus B acts on R/R0 of type (hamil) in this case.

Otherwise we have that R0Φ([P,B]) and therefore R/R0 is elementary abelian of order 4 or 8. Moreover B acts irreducibly on [R/R0,B], which is a group of order 4. In addition every proper subgroup of B centralizes R/R0. Consequently, if R/R0=[R/R0,B], then B acts on R/R0 of type (std) or of type (cent).

The final case is that B is not nilpotent, and we suppose that B acts of type (NN) on P. Then Definition 4.16 yields that B acts irreducibly on P. Hence there is nothing left to prove.

Suppose that B acts of type (Cy). Then we choose a Sylow subgroup Q of B such that B=B(B)Q. Then [R/R0,B(B)]=[R,B(B)]=[P,B(B)]=1 and Q acts on P avoiding L9 in such a way that Φ(Q)=Z(B) does not centralize P. Then Lemma 5.5 yields that Φ(Q) does not centralize R. In particular, we have that [R/R0,Z(B)]1. In addition Q acts on R/R0 avoiding L9, by our arguments above. Altogether B acts on R/R0 avoiding L9 of type (Cy) in this final case. □

6 The first implication

We now investigate the general case.

Proposition 6.1.

Let G be a finite L9-free group. Then G = NK, where N is a nilpotent normal Hall-subgroup of G with modular Sylow subgroups and K is a batten group. Moreover, for all pπ(N), every batten of K acts on Op(N) avoiding L9 or it centralizes Op(N).

Proof.

We first remark that G is L10-free, whence Theorem A of [Citation9] implies that G is soluble. Furthermore, Corollary C of [Citation9] provides normal Hall-subgroups N and M of G such that NM and such that N is nilpotent, M/N is a 2-group and G/M is metacyclic. We choose N as large as possible with these constraints. From Lemma 4.1 we see that N1. We also have that every Sylow subgroup of N is L9-free, and hence it is modular by Lemma 4.2. In addition the Schur-Zassenhaus Theorem (see for example 3.3.1. of [Citation5]) provides a complement K of N in G.

(1) If RQ is a non-nilpotent Hall {r, q}-subgroup of K, where R is a normal Sylow r-subgroup of RQ and QSylq(RQ), then RQ is a batten. For all pπ(N), the group RQ centralizes Op(N) or acts on it avoiding L9.

Proof. If there is some pπ(N) such that [Op(N),R]1, then we set P:=Op(N). Otherwise the maximal choice of N implies that R is not a normal subgroup of K. Then, using the solubility of G, we find a prime sπ(K){r} and a normal s-subgroup T of K such that [T,R]1 (see 5.2.2 of [Citation5]). Then sq because 1[R,Q]R and 1[T,R]T. In this case we set P:=T.

In both cases p,r and q are pairwise different primes and PRQ is a non-nilpotent {p, r, q}-subgroup that satisfies the hypothesis of Proposition 4.15. For this we note that PEPRQPNG(R) and RNG(Q). Since [R,Q]1, the assertion in (1) follows. □

(2) Every Sylow subgroup S of K is a batten, and for all pπ(N) it is true that S centralizes Op(N) or acts on Op(N) avoiding L9.

Proof. Let S be a Sylow subgroup of K. If S centralizes N, then the choice of N provides some Sylow subgroup R of K such that RS is not nilpotent. Then (1) implies that RS is a batten, then that S is cyclic and hence that S is a batten.

Let pπ(N/CN(S)). Then Op(N)S is an L9-free {p, q}-group for some prime q. Hence Corollary 4.10 implies the assertion. □

(3) K is a batten group.

Proof. Let 1BK be such that there is some K1K such that K=K1×B, where (|K1|,|B|)=1 and B is not a direct product of nontrivial subgroups of coprime order. In particular B is a Hall subgroup of K. If B is nilpotent, then B is a Sylow q-subgroup of K for some prime q. In this case (2) implies that B is a batten.

Assume for a contradiction that B is not a batten of K. Then B is not nilpotent and therefore (1) yields that |B| is divisible by at least three different primes. Since BG is L9-free, Lemma 4.1 provides a normal Sylow r-subgroup R of B for some prime rπ(B). We remark that R is a normal subgroup of K=K1×B. In addition B is is not a direct product of non-trivial subgroups with coprime order and hence there are a prime qπ(B) and some QSylq(B) such that RQ is not nilpotent. Now B is a Hall subgroup of K and thus RQ is a Hall subgroup of K. In particular (1) implies that RQ is a batten and it follows that |R|=r and 1CQ(R)=Φ(Q). We further see, from Definition 4.16 and (1), that for every pπ(N) with the property [Op(N),R]1 we have that |Op(N)|=pq. Since R is a normal Sylow subgroup of K, the maximal choice of N provides some pπ(N) such that R does not centralize P:=Op(N). In particular we have that |P|=pq.

Let sπ(B){q,r} and let S be a Sylow s-subgroup of B such that QS = SQ. Such a subgroup exists by Satz VI. 2.3 in [Citation3]. If S does not centralize R, then RS is not nilpotent and therefore our arguments above show that ps=|P|=pq. This is impossible because rs. Consequently [R,S]=1.

Since B is directly indecomposable, we conclude that SQ is not nilpotent. But SQ is a Hall subgroup of B and then it is a Hall subgroup of K. In particular (1) yields that SQ is a batten. From the fact that 1CQ(R)=Φ(Q) we conclude that |Q|q, and then |S|=s and SE SQ. In addition CQ(S)=Φ(Q)=CQ(R). But (R×S)Q is an L9-free group, and this situation contradicts Corollary 4.13. □

We conclude that, by construction, G = NK, where N is a nilpotent normal subgroup of G with modular Sylow subgroups and K is a batten group, by (3), such that for all pπ(N) it is true that every batten of K centralizes Op(N) or acts on Op(N) avoiding L9, by (1) and (2). □

The converse of Proposition 6.1 is false, as can be seen in the following example and subsequent lemma.

Example 6.2.

Let H=C19×C19J=C5×C5 and let x,yGL(2,19)×GL(2,5) be such that x=((1001),(0310)) and y=((4004),(2312)).

Then xy=((4004),(3123))=yx. Hence G:=(H×J)(x×y) is a group.

Moreover, N:=H×J is a nilpotent normal subgroup of G with modular Sylow subgroups. Since x8=(x2)4=((1001),(3003))4=((1001),(1001))2=1

and

y9=((7007),(1001))3, it follows that x and y have coprime order.

Thus K:=x×y is cyclic, which means that it is a batten group.

We see that x and y induce non-trivial power automorphisms on H. Thus every batten of K acts on H=O19(N) avoiding L19 of type (std). In addition x2 and y3 induce power automorphisms on J. Since x and y act irreducibly on J, it follows that every batten of K acts on J=O5(N) avoiding L19 of type (std), too.

Altogether G satisfies the conclusion of Proposition 6.1.

On the other hand we observe that π(K)={2,3}=π(x,y/x2)=π(K/CK(H)) and that CH(CK(J))=CH(y3)=1.

If gHJ centralizes x or y, then g = 1. Thus the following lemma yields that G is not L9-free.

Lemma 6.3.

Let H be a non-trivial abelian group where all non-trivial Sylow subgroups are non-cyclic elementary abelian, let L be a cyclic group inducing power automorphism on H such that π(L)=π(L/CL(H)) and let 1J be an abelian group admitting L as a group of automorphisms such that the action of L on Op(J) avoids L9 for every pπ(J) and such that (|H|,|J|)=1.

Let π:={qπ(L)|COq(L)(H)<COq(L)(J)}. Suppose that CH(CL(J))=1 and, for all g(H×J)#, suppose that g centralizes neither Oπ(L) nor Oπ(L).

Then (H×J)L is not L9-free.

Proof.

We first set L1:=Oπ(L) and L2:=Oπ(L). Since none of the groups L1 nor L2 is centralized by any element of HJ{1}, it follows that L1 and L2 are both non-trivial.

For every odd prime pπ(H) there is an elementary abelian subgroup Hp of H that has order p2. In particular there are elements ap and bp of H such that Hp=ap×bp.

We set a:=pπ(H)ap and b:=pπ(H)bp.

These elements are well-defined (in the sense that the ordering of the primes does not matter) because H is abelian. For every pπ(J), we further see that L acts on Op(J) avoiding L9. Since J is abelian, we deduce from Lemma 5.3(b) that [Op(J),L] is elementary abelian. In addition L acts irreducibly on [Op(J),L] or it induces power automorphisms on Op(L), by Lemma 5.4. We choose xp[Op(J),L]#. Then L acts irreducibly on P:=xpL. Next we choose lL such that L=l. Then 1xplPHJ and 1[l,xp]PHJ. Thus our hypothesis implies that 1[[l,xp],L1]P and 1[xpl,L2]P. Altogether we have that P=xpL=(xpl)L=[[l,xp],L1]L=[xpl,L2]L. Moreover, Lemma 5.5 yields that CL(xp)=CL(P)=CL(Op(J)).

For every pπ(L) we choose 1xp[Op(J),L], and then we set x:=pπ(J)xp.

Since J is abelian, it follows that CL(J)=pπ(J)CL(Op(J))=pπ(J)CL(xp)=CL(x). Next we set y:=xl. Then our previous arguments show that J0:=xL=yL=[[l,x],L1]L=[y,L2]L (*).

We will construct a subgroup lattice L9 using Lemma 3.5. For this we set E:=CL(HJ)E HJL and D:=CL(J).

For every qπ we have COq(L)(H)COq(L)(J) and so COq(L)(J)E. This implies that CL2(J)=CL2(HJ)E () and that D=CL(J)=CL1(J). We conclude that CL1(x)E=(L1CL(x))E=(L1CL(J))E=CL1(J)E=DE=D.

If qπ=π(L1), then COq(L)(H)<COq(L)(J)CL1(x) and therefore CL1(H)=CL1(HJ)E (). Then it follows that EL1=CL1(HJ)=CL1(H)<CL1(x)DL1. In particular ED and hence (L9(i)) of Lemma 3.5 holds.

Next we set A:=aL1xES:=L1axE and T:=L1a1xE. Then we have that A contains the subgroups S, T and D (=CL1(x)E). In addition, if c{a,a1,a2}, then we see that c=a, because o(a) is odd by construction. Since Ca(D)CH(D)=CH(CL(J))=1, it follows that a=c=[c,D]×Ca(D)=[c,D], by Lemma 1.1. The group L1 induces power automorphisms on H, which means that it normalizes [c,D]. Together with Part (d) of Lemma 1.4 we conclude that D,L1cE=[c,D]L1cEL1cE=[c,D]L1cE=cL1E=Ax1.

In particular, since D centralizes x, it follows that D,T=D,S=A. Moreover, we have that AT,S=L1,L1a2Ea1xD,L1a2Ea1x=(Ax1)a1x=A and therefore we conclude that S,T=A as well. Next Lemma 5.5 gives that CL1(a)=CL1(H)E by (). Furthermore L1c is a π-group for all c{a,a1,a2}, whence L1EL1cOπ(L1E)L1c=L1L1c=CL1(c)=CL1(a)Eby Part (b) of Lemma 1.4. Altogether Dedekind’s modular law gives that L1EL1cE=(L1EL1c)EE for all c{a,a1,a2}. We conclude that TS=L1axEL1a1xEEx=E, that DT(L1EL1a1E)xEx=E and that DS(L1EL1aE)xE. With all these properties, we see that (L9(ii)) of Lemma 3.5 is true.

Now we set C:=bDL2 and U:=bL2E. Then C=D,U and DU=CL(J)bL2E=(CL(J)bL2)E=CL2(J)E by Dedekind’s modular law and by Part (b) of Lemma 1.4. Hence () implies that (L9(iii)) of Lemma 3.5 holds.

Let c{a,a1} and let X:=L1cx,L2. Then X contains a π-Hall subgroup as well as a π(L2)-Hall subgroup of HJL. Since HJL is soluble, there is a π(L)-Hall subgroup K of X such that L2K and some gHJ such that Lg=K. It follows that L2KL=LgL=CL(g) by Lemma 1.4(b). The hypothesis of our lemma yields that g = 1 and therefore L=KX. From there we obtain some hX such that L1h=L1cx and hence L1=L1L1hx1c1CL(hx1c1) by Lemma 1.4(b). This forces cx=hX, and then c,xX, because H and J have coprime order and centralize each other. Altogether c=a and xL=J0 are subgroups of X, and we conclude that X=aJ0L. Thus U,T=L1a1x,bL2E=bL1a1x,L2,E=bXE=a,bJ0L=bL1ax,L2,E=U,L.

We set F:=a,bJ0L in order to obtain Part (L9(iv)) of Lemma 3.5. Moreover, Dedekind’s law and Part (a) of Lemma 1.4 gives that AC=aL1xEbDL2=(aL1xEbL2)D=(a(L1EL2)xb(L1EL2))D=(aCL2(HJ)xbCL2(HJ))D=(aCL2(HJ)bCL2(HJ))D=(abCL2(HJ))CL2(HJ)D=CL2(HJ)D=D.

We set B:=abLy. Then AB=(aL1EabLyx1)x(a(L1EHLyx1))x(aCL1E(yx1))x(aCL(J))x=aDby Lemma 1.4(b), because (yx1)LHJH=1.

In a similar way we obtain that ABabD and therefore DABaDabD=(aabD)D=D.

We further calculate that BC=abLybDL2ab(LyHDL2)abCDL2(y)abCL(J)=abDand similarly BCbD. Therefore DBCabDbD=(abbD)D=D.

Finally (*) and Part (d) of Lemma 1.4 yield that A,B=aL1xE,abLy=a,bL1xE,Ly=a,b[yx1,L1]LL=a,b[[l,x],L1]LL=a,bJ0L=F=a,b[y,L2]LL=a,bLy,DL2=abLy,bDL2=B,C.

Altogether {A,B,C,D,E,F,S,T,U} satisfies every condition of Lemma 3.5, which means that it is isomorphic to L9. □

The previous lemma and Lemma 4.12 motivate the following definition:

Definition 6.4.

Here we define a class L of finite groups, and each group in L has a type.

We say that GL has type (N, K) if and only if the following hold:

(L1) G=NK, where N is a normal nilpotent Hall subgroup of G with modular Sylow subgroups and K is a batten group.

(L2)If pπ(N), then every batten of K centralizes Op(N) or it acts on it avoiding L9.

(L3)For all Sylow subgroups Q of K and all distinct Sylow subgroups P and R of N that are not centralized by Q, we have that CQ(P)CQ(R).

(L4)Suppose that HN is abelian, that its nontrivial Sylow subgroups are not cyclic and that LPotK(H) is cyclic and such that π(L)=π(L/CL(H)). Let 1JN be L-invariant and abelian, suppose that (|H|,|J|)=1[H,J]=1 and CH(CL(J))=1, and set π:={qπ(L)|COq(L)(H)<COq(L)(J)}.

Then there is some g(HJ)# that centralizes Oπ(L) or Oπ(L).

Theorem 6.5.

Let G be a finite L9-free group. Then GL.

Proof.

From Lemma 6.1 we see that G = NK and that (L1) and (L2) are satisfied.

For (L3) we let Q be a Sylow subgroup of K and we let P and R be distinct Sylow subgroups of N that are not centralized by Q. Since N is a nilpotent normal Hall subgroup of G, it follows that [P,R]=1 and that Q normalizes P and R. Then (P×R)Q is directly indecomposable and L9-free, whence Corollary 4.13 gives that CQ(P)CQ(R).

Finally, we look at (L4) and we assume that it is not true. Then there is an abelian subgroup H of N such that the nontrivial Sylow subgroups are not cyclic, and we find a cyclic group LPotK(H) such that π(L)=π(L/CL(H)) and a nontrivial L-invariant abelian subgroup J of N such that (|H|,|J|)=1[H,J]=1 and CH(CL(J))=1. Let π:={qπ(L)|COq(L)(H)<COq(L)(J)}. Then we have, for all g(HJ)#, that g centralizes neither Oπ(L) nor Oπ(L) for π:={qπ(L)|COq(L)(H)<COq(L)(J)}.

We note that P does not centralize Oπ(L)L. Then we find a prime qπ(L) such that a Sylow q-subgroup Q of L does not centralize P. Using Lemma 5.2, we see that Q acts on Op(N) avoiding L9 and then Lemma 5.7 yields that Q acts non-trivially on P, and avoiding L9. Now we may apply Corollary 5.6: Since L induces power automorphisms on P, Part (c) shows that P is elementary abelian. Then the hypotheses of Lemma 6.3 are satisfied. It says that (H×J)L is not L9-free, which is false. We conclude that (L 4) holds. □

7 The class L

Lemma 7.1.

All groups in the class L are soluble.

Proof.

Let GL be of type (N, K). Then N is nilpotent normal Hall subgroup of G and G/NK is a direct product of p-groups or of groups whose order is divisible by exactly two primes. Thus G/N is soluble as well, and it follows that G is soluble. □

Lemma 7.2.

Let GL be of type (N, K) and π:=π([N,K]). Then every subgroup of Oπ(N) is normal in N.

Proof.

Let U be a subgroup of Oπ(N). Then UEN if and only if Op(U)EOp(N) for all pπ, since N is nilpotent. Let pπ. We note that this implies that Op(N) is not centralized by K. In particular there is a batten of K that acts non-trivially on Op(N) and avoiding L9. If Op(N) is abelian, then Op(U)EOp(N). If Op(N) is not abelian, then we apply Lemma 4.17 (b) to a batten B of K that acts non-trivially on Op(N). The first possibility described there implies that Op(N) is abelian, which is not the case here. Thus the second possibility holds, and then Op(N)Q8×I, where I is cyclic of order at most 2. We conclude that Op(N) is hamiltonian and it follows that Op(U)\unlhdOp(N). □

Lemma 7.3.

Let GL be of type (N, K) and XG. Then there is some x[N,K] such that X=(NX)(KxX).

Proof.

We set M:=NX. Then M is a normal Hall subgroup of X, because N is one of G. Then the Schur-Zassenhaus Theorem provides a complement C of M in X, and we notice that C and M have coprime orders. Therefore π(C)=π(X)π(M)π(G)π(N)=π(K). It follows that C is contained in a complement for N in G. Since G is soluble by Lemma 7.1, such a complement is conjugate to K, and thus we find gG such that CKg. The coprime action of K on N yields, together with Lemma 1.1, that N=CN(K)[N,K], and therefore G=KN=KCN(K)[N,K]. We notice that [N,KEG and we let x[N,K] and yKCN(K)NG(K) be such that g = yx. Then C=KgX=KxX and hence X=MC=(NC)(KxX). □

Lemma 7.4.

Let GL be of type (N, K) and suppose that UG. Then U is a group in class L of type (UN,UKg) for some g[N,K].

Proof.

Lemma 7.3 provides some g[N,K] such that U=(UN)·(UKg). By conjugation we may suppose that g = 1 and we set K1:=UK. Then Lemma 2.7 yields that K1=UKgKgK is a batten group. Moreover, M:=UNN is a normal nilpotent Hall subgroup of U with modular Sylow subgroups, by (L 1). This means that (L 1) holds for U, and now we turn to (L 2) and let pπ(M). Suppose that B is a batten of K1 that does not centralize Op(M). Then it does not centralize Op(N) and therefore Lemma 5.2 implies that BB/1 acts on Op(N) avoiding L9. Then we may apply Lemma 5.7 to see that B also acts on Op(M)/1Op(M) avoiding L9.

This gives property (L2) of Definition 6.4 for U, and (L4) follows because MN and K1K.

For (L 3) we let Q1 be a Sylow subgroup of K1 and we let p,rπ(M) be different primes such that [Op(M),Q1]1[Or(M),Q1]. We need to prove that CQ1(Op(M))CQ1(Or(M)).

First we let Q be a Sylow subgroup of K that contains Q1. Then [Op(N),Q]1[Or(N),Q] and therefore CQ(Op(N))CQ(Or(N)), using Property (L 3) for G. In particular, these centralizers cannot both be trivial, and we may suppose that CQ(Op(N))1. Then Q does not act faithfully on Op(N), but the action of Q on Op(N) avoids L9. Definition 4.8 immediately gives that QQ8. Then it follows that Q is cyclic, which means that the subgroup lattice L(Q) of Q is a chain, and Q1 is also cyclic.

We assume for a contradiction that CQ1(Op(M))=CQ1(Or(M)). Then Lemma 5.5, with Q1 in the role of H, Op(M) in the role of R and Op(N) in the role of P, gives that CQ1(Op(M))=CQ1(Op(N)). Similarly CQ1(Or(M))=CQ1(Or(N)), and then it follows that CQ1(Op(N))=CQ1(Or(N)). We recall that CQ(Op(N))CQ(Or(N)) and that Q is cyclic, and now we may suppose that CQ(Op(N))CQ(Or(N)). This forces CQ1(Op(N))CQ(Op(N)), which is impossible. Thus CQ1(Op(M))CQ1(Or(M)) and (L 3) holds for U as well. □

Lemma 7.5.

Let GL be of type (N, K) and suppose that S is a normal Sylow q-subgroup of K that centralizes N for some prime q. Let K1 be a Hall q-subgroup of K.

Then G is also of type (N×S,K1). In particular, if we choose (N, K) such that |N| is as large as possible, then π(K)=π(K/CK(N)).

Proof.

We show that G=(N×S)K1 satisfies (L1)–(L4) of Definition 6.4, and we first note that K1 is a batten group by Lemma 2.7. The structure of K forces all Sylow subgroups of K to be cyclic or quaternion, more specifically S is cyclic or isomorphic to Q8. This means that S is modular. Since S is a normal Sylow q-subgroup of K and N is a Hall subgroup of G, by hypothesis, it follows that N × S is a Hall subgroup of G where all Sylow subgroups are modular.

By hypothesis [N,S]=1 and N is nilpotent, hence N × S is nilpotent, too. This is (L1).

For (L2) we let B be a batten of K1 and pπ(N×S). We keep in mind that B is not necessarily a batten of K – if it is, then it centralizes Op(N×S) or it acts on it avoiding L9, because of (L2) for G.

Now we suppose that B is not a batten of K and that [Op(N×S),B]1. Then SB is a non-nilpotent batten of K. If pq, then SB acts on Op(N) avoiding L9, and [Op(N),S]=1. Then Definition 4.16 implies that SB acts of type (Cy) and it follows that B acts on Op(N) avoiding L9. Finally suppose that q = p. Then Φ(B) centralizes S=Op(NS), while B induces power automorphisms on the cyclic group S of order p. Thus SB satisfies (std) of Definition 4.6, and we deduce that B acts on S avoiding L9.

We turn to (L3). Let Q be a Sylow subgroup of K1 and let P and R be distinct Sylow subgroups of N × S that are not centralized by Q. First we note that Q is a Sylow subgroup of K because K1 is a Hall subgroup of K by hypothesis. Therefore, if PRN, then we immediately have that CQ(R)CQ(P), by (L3) in G.

Without loss suppose that RN, i.e. R = S. Then we recall that Q was chosen not to centralize P and R = S, which means that Q and S cannot come from distinct battens of K, but their product must be a non-nilpotent batten of K. Moreover, [P,QS]1. We obtain from Lemma 2.5 and Definition 4.16 that Φ(Q)=Z(Q)=CQ(S) does not centralize P and therefore CQ(R)CQ(P). This is (L3).

Finally, let HN×S be such that its nontrivial Sylow subgroups are not cyclic, let LPotK1(H) be cyclic and such that π(L)=π(L/CL(H)) and let 1J be an L-invariant abelian subgroup of M such that (|H|,|J|)=1, [H,J]=1 and CH(CL(J))=1.

As K is a batten group, the set π(K/CK(S)) contains at most one element. We recall that LK1K, and then it follows that, for every set of primes π, the group S centralizes Oπ(L) or Oπ(L). In order to prove (L4) of Definition 6.4, we may thus suppose that H and J are subgroups of N.

Then LK1K shows that LPotK(H). Hence we apply (L4) of Definition 6.4 to G, i.e. to the type (N, K). If π:={qπ(L)|COq(L)(H)<COq(L)(J)}, then we find some g(HJ)# that centralizes Oπ(L) or Oπ(L).

Altogether, G=(N×S)K1 satisfies Definition 6.4.

We now suppose that |N| is as large as possible and we assume for a contradiction that SCK(N) is a Sylow subgroup of K. Then S is not normal in K, hence there is a non-nilpotent batten B of K such that B=B(B)S. For all pπ(N) it follows that [Op(N),Z(B)][Op(N),S]=1, by Lemma 2.5. Then Definition 4.16 yields that B does not act on Op(N) avoiding L9, whence B centralizes Op(N). But now B(B)CK(N) and B(B) is a normal Sylow subgroup of K. This contradicts the maximal choice of N. □

Lemma 7.6.

Let GL and suppose that MEG. Then G/ML.

Proof.

By induction we may suppose that M is a minimal normal subgroup of G. We recall that G is soluble by Lemma 7.1, and we let r be prime such that M is an elementary abelian r-group. If M has a complement C in G, then G/MC and Lemma 7.4 gives that CL and hence G/ML.

Consequently we may suppose that M does not have a complement in G. We choose N,KG such that G has type (N, K) and such that |N| is as large as possible. Then π(K)=π(K/CK(N)) by Lemma 7.5.

First suppose that rπ(K). Then MK and we see that [N,M]NMNK=1, because N is a Hall subgroup of G. Hence MCK(N). Next we let B be a batten of K that contains M. Then MCB(N), which means that for all pπ(N), B does not act faithfully on Op(N).

Since there is some pπ(N) such that B acts on Op(N) avoiding L9, it follows from Definition 4.8 that B is not isomorphic to Q8. In addition MZ(B), if B is not nilpotent, by Definition 5.1. Therefore, in this case, the section B/M is a non-nilpotent batten as well. We conclude that K/M is a batten group.

Assume for a contradiction that rπ(N), but that MCN(K). Then we note that CM(K)EG by Lemma 7.2, and we deduce that CM(K)=1, because M is a minimal normal subgroup of G. This forces M[Or(N),K]. Then [Or(N),K] is not elementary abelian, because otherwise M would have a complement in this commutator and hence in G. But we are working under the hypothesis that it does not.

Now Lemmas 5.4 and 4.17(b) imply that M[Or(N),K]Q8. But now Z([Or(N),K]) is the unique subgroup of order 2 of [Or(N),K], which means that it must be centralized by K and contained in M. But this is a contradiction. Thus MCN(K) and Corollary 5.6 implies that p = 2. We summarise that MCK(N) and that K/M is a batten group or MCN(K) and p = 2.

Let :GG/M be the natural homomorphism. Then G¯=N¯·K¯, where N¯ is a normal nilpotent Hall subgroup of G with modular Sylow subgroups, since sections of modular p-subgroups are modular. Moreover K¯ is a batten group. Thus G¯ satisfies (L1) of Definition 6.4. We further deduce (L2) from Lemmas 5.2 and 5.7.

For (L3) we let Q be a Sylow subgroup of K and we let p,sπ(N¯) be distinct primes such that [Os(N¯),Q¯][Op(N¯),Q¯]. Then [Os(N),Q][Op(N),Q] and therefore CQ(Os(N))CQ(Op(N)). Since MCN(Q) or MCK(Os(N))CK(Op(N)), it follows that CQ¯(Os(N¯))CQ¯(Op(N¯)).

We finally let 1H¯N¯ be abelian with non-cyclic Sylow subgroups and L¯PotK¯(H¯) be cyclic with π(L¯)=π(L¯/CL¯(H¯)) and we let J¯ be an abelian L¯-invariant subgroup of N¯ such that (|H¯|,|J¯|)=1 and CH¯(CL¯(J¯))=1. We set π¯:={qπ(L¯)|Q¯Sylq(L¯):CQ¯(H¯)<CQ¯(J¯)}.

Then we assume for a contradiction that every nontrivial element g¯H¯J¯ centralizes neither Oπ(L¯) nor Oπ(L¯). Then Lemma 1.1 yields that [H¯J¯,L¯]=H¯J¯. We choose pre-images H, L and J in G of smallest possible order. Then HJ=[HJ,L] and π(X¯)=π(X) for all X{HLJ}, because G is soluble by Lemma 7.1. In particular we have that (|H|,|J|)=1.

If rπ(X) for some X{H,J}, then r = 2. Then our assumption implies that CO2(X)(L)M. It follows that XX¯ or that MΦ(X)=Φ([X,L]). In the second case, we apply Lemmas 5.4 and 4.17. Together they show that [O2(N),K]=[O2(N),L]Q8 and thus π(L/CO2(N)(L))={3}. This means that O2(N) centralizes Oπ(L) or Oπ(L). But then we also have that [O2(X¯),Oσ(L¯)]=1 for some σ{π,π}, which is a contradiction. We deduce that H¯H and J¯J. In particular HN is abelian, with non-cyclic Sylow subgroups, and J1 is an abelian L-invariant subgroup of N. Since L¯ is cyclic, it follows from our arguments above that L is also cyclic. Moreover π(L)=π(L¯)=π(L¯/CL¯(H¯))=π(L/CL(H)), because MCK(N) or ML=1.

We now investigate the action of L on H. Since H¯H and ML=1 or MCL(H), we see that L induces power automorphisms on H. In addition Lemma 1.1 shows that CH(CL(J))¯CH¯(CL(J)¯)CH¯(CL¯(J¯))=1and then the fact that HM=1 yields that CH(CL(J))=1. Altogether we obtain, by applying (L4) to G, some gHJ# such that g centralizes Oπ(L) or Oπ(L), where π:={qπ(L)|QSylq(L):CQ(H)<CQ(J)}. Since H¯J¯HJ, it follows that g¯1 and [Oπ(L¯),g¯]=1 or [Oπ(L¯),g¯]=1. Again we use that L¯ acts on H¯H and J¯L equivalently to L, because MLCL(N). Then we see that π¯:={qπ(L¯)|Q¯Sylq(L¯):CQ¯(H¯)<CQ¯(J¯)}=π.

This is a contradiction. □

Lemma 7.7.

Let GL be of type (N, K) such that CK(N)=1, let qπ(K) and let QSylq(K). Then 1[N,Ω1(Q)] has prime power order.

Proof.

We apply Lemma 7.4 and we see that NΩ1(Q)L has type (N,Ω1(Q)). Since Ω1(Q) does not centralize N, there is a prime pπ(N) such that [Op(N),Ω1(Q)]1. It follows that CΩ1(Q)(Op(N))=1. Now (L3) implies that Ω1(Q) centralizes Or(N) for every rπ(N){p}, and this shows that 1[N,Ω1(Q)][Op(N),Ω1(Q)]Op(N). □

Lemma 7.8.

Let GL be of type (N, K) such that CK(N)=1, let qπ(K) and let QSylq(K). Let pπ(N) be such that Ω1(Q) does not centralize P:=Op(N). Then the following hold:

  1. NG(Ω1(Q))=(Op(N)K)×CP(K).

  2. G=[P,Ω1(Q)]NG(Ω1(Q)).

  3. [P,Ω1(Q)]=[P,K] acts transitively on Ω1(Q)G={Q0G||Q0|=q}.

  4. If XG, then there is some x[P,Ω1(Q)] such that X=(XP)NX(Ω1(Q)x).

  5. Suppose that XG, that q divides |X| and that xP. Then X=(XP)NX(Ω1(Q)x) if and only if Ω1(Q)xX.

Proof.

We set P0:=[P,Ω1(Q)]. Then Lemma 7.7 implies that P0=[N,Ω1(Q)] and so Op(N)CG(Ω1(Q))NG(Ω1(Q)). Furthermore K acts on P avoiding L9 and then we have that P0=[P,Q]=[P,K] by Lemma 5.4. Next KNG(Ω1(Q)) from Lemma 2.6.

Since N is nilpotent, we conclude that NG(Ω1(Q))=(Op(N)×NP(Ω1(Q)))K. But we also have that [NP(Ω1(Q)),Ω1(Q)]PΩ1(Q)=1, whence NP(Ω1(Q))CP(Ω1(Q))=CP(K) by Lemma 5.5. Consequently NP(Ω1(Q))=CP(Ω1(Q)) and it follows that NG(Ω1(Q))=(Op(N)K)×CP(K), as stated in (a).

For (b) we recall that, by (a), the subgroups K and Op(N) normalize Ω1(Q). Then G=POp(N)KPNG(Q)G. Moreover P EG and Lemma 1.1 implies that P=CP(Ω1(Q))P0, where CP(Ω1(Q))NG(Ω1(Q)) and therefore G=P0NG(Ω1(Q)) as stated in (b).

From there we deduce that P0 acts transitively on Ω1(Q)G by conjugation. The second statement of (c) follows because G is soluble (Lemma 7.1), together with the fact that Ω1(Q) is the unique subgroup of its order in the Hall subgroup K of G (Lemma 2.6). This means that every subgroup of order q of G is conjugate to Ω1(Q), completing (c).

For (d) and (e) we let XG. Lemma 7.3 provides some gG such that X=(NX)(KgX). Moreover, (a) implies that Kg and Op(N)(=Op(N)g) normalize Ω1(Q)g, and then we summarise: X=(NX)(KgX)(PX)(Op(N)X)(KgX)(PX)NX(Ω1(Q)g)X.

Using (b) we see that G=NG(Ω1(Q))P0, and then we take yNG(Ω1(Q)) and xP0 such that g = yx. Now we deduce that X=(PX)NX(Ω1(Q)yx)=(PX)NX(Ω1(Q)x), as stated in (d).

Finally, suppose that q divides |X| and that xP. Suppose first that X=(XP)NX(Qx). Then q divides |NX(Ω1(Q)x)|, which provides a subgroup Q0 of order q in NX(Ω1(Q)x)NG(Ω1(Q)x) and, by (d), there is some yP0 such that Ω1(Q)y=Q0NG(Ω1(Q)x)=NG(Ω1(Q))x. Then Ω1(Q) and Ω1(Q)yx1 are subgroups of NG(Ω1(Q)) and therefore [yx1,Ω1(Q)]=[[yx1,Ω1(Q)],Ω1(Q)][[P,Ω1(Q)]NG(Ω1(Q)),Ω1(Q)][CP(Ω1(Q)),Ω1(Q)]=1by Lemma 1.1. We conclude that Ω1(Q)x=Ω1(Q)y=Q0NX(Ω1(Q)x)X.

Now, conversely, suppose that Ω1(Q)xX. Then (d) provides some zP0 such that X=(PX)(NX(Ω1(Q)z)). In the paragraph above we have shown that Ω1(Q)zX. We apply (c) to X=(XN)(XKg), which is a group in L by Lemma 7.4, and we obtain some yPX such that Ω1(Q)zy=Ω1(Q)x. We conclude that X=Xy=(PX)y(NXy(Ω1(Q)zy))=(PX)(NX(Ω1(Q)x)),because PXEX. □

Lemma 7.9.

Let GL be of type (N, K) and let pπ(N) such that K induces non-trivial power automorphisms on P:=Op(N).

Then for all XYG, there is some i{0,1} such that |X,YP|=|(PX)(PY)|·pi.

In addition i = 0 if and only if there is some gP such that for both Z{X,Y} we have Z(ZP)Op(N)Kg.

Proof.

We first remark that Lemma 7.2 gives that every subgroup of P is normal in N, and hence in G, because K normalizes every subgroup of P as well. In addition P=[P,K] is elementary abelian by Corollary 5.6 (c).

Let XYG. Then Lemma 7.3 provides x,yP such that X(XP)Op(N)Kx and Y(YP)Op(N)Ky.

This implies that X,Y(XP)(YP)x1yOp(N)Kx, bearing in mind that XP and YP are normal subgroups of G, and therefore X,YP=(PX)(PY)x1y.

Since P is elementary abelian, we see that o(xy1){1,p} and we deduce the first assertion.

If it is possible to choose x = y, then X,YP=(PX)(PY)x1y=(PX)(PY) and in particular i = 0 in the statement of the lemma.

For the converse we suppose that i = 0, i.e. |X,YP|=|(PX)(PY)|. Then x1yX,YP=(PX)(PY) and thus we find x0XP and y0YP such that x1y=x0y0. Then g:=yy01=xx0PXY. We note that x0 normalizes X, centralizes PX and normalizes Op(N), which implies that X=Xx0((XP)Op(N)Kx)x0=(XP)Op(N)Kxx0. Similarly Y(YP)Op(N)Kyy01. □

Lemma 7.10.

Let GL be of type (N, K). Suppose that X and Y are subgroups of G such that X,Y=G and let B is a batten of K. Suppose that K has a normal q-complement H. Then one of the following hold:

  1. q|G:X|,

  2. q|G:Y|, or

  3. q = 2, K has a section isomorphic to Q8 and 4 divides (|X|,|Y|).

Proof.

Let QSylq(K) and suppose that q divides neither |G:X| nor q||G:Y|. Then Lemma 7.3 gives maximal subgroups MX and MY of Q such that XNHMX and YNHMY.

If Q is cyclic, then MY=MX=Φ(Q) and it follows that G=X,YNHΦ(Q)NHQ=G. This is impossible. We conclude that Q is not cyclic and then, since K is a batten group, it follows that QQ8. We assume for a contradiction that 4|X|. Then XNHΦ(Q) and hence G=X,YNHMYNHQ=G, which is again a contradiction. □

Lemma 7.11.

Let GL be of type (N, K) such that K acts irreducibly on [Op(N),K]/Φ([Op(N),K]) for some prime pπ(N). If X,YG are such that X,Y=G, then X or Y acts irreducibly on [Op(N),K]/Φ([Op(N),K]).

Proof.

Let X,YG be such that X,Y=G and let P:=Op(N). We assume for a contradiction that neither X nor Y act irreducibly on [P,K]/Φ([P,K]). Lemma 7.2 implies that N normalizes every subgroup of P (*). Moreover, by Lemma 7.3, there are x,yN such that X=(XN)(XKx) and Y=(XN)(YKy) and, by assumption, neither XKx nor YKy act irreducibly on [P,K]/Φ([P,K]). It follows from Lemma 5.4 that XKx and YKy both induce power automorphisms on P and that |P|p. Thus (*) yields that X and Y normalize every subgroup of P. Then also G=X,Y normalizes every subgroup of P, which contradicts the irreducible action of K. □

8 The main result

Theorem 8.1.

If GL, then G is L9-free.

Proof.

Assume for a contradiction that the statement is false and let G be a minimal counterexample. Then there is a sublattice L={E,S,T,D,U,A,B,C,F} of L(G) isomorphic to L9, and in particular L satisfies the relations in Definition 3.1.

We let G be of type (N, K) where, among the minimal counterexamples, we choose G such that |N| is as large as possible and we set π(K)*:=π(K){|B(H)||H is a non‐nilpotent batten of K}.

Then K has a normal q-complement for every qπ(K)* and Lemma 7.10 is applicable.

We will first analyze how L fits into the subgroup lattice of G.

(1) F = G, CK(N)=1 and every subgroup of N is normal in N.

Proof. The group F is a subgroup of G that is not L9-free, and Lemma 7.4 yields that FL. Hence the minimal choice of G implies that F = G.

Similarly, it follows from Lemma 3.4 that G is not a direct product of two non-trivial groups of coprime order. Let pπ(N). Then N=Op(N)×Op(N) because N is nilpotent. If K centralizes Op(N), then G=Op(N)K×Op(N), where the direct factors have coprime order by (L1). But we just saw above that such a direct decomposition of G is not possible. Therefore [Op(N),K]1 and p divides |[Op(N),K]|, which divides |[N,K]|. We conclude from Lemma 7.2 that every subgroup of Op(N) is normal in N. This implies that every subgroup of N is a normal subgroup of N, because N is nilpotent.

Since we have chosen N as large as possible, Lemma 7.5 implies that π(K)=π(K/CK(N)). Let qπ(CK(N)). Then the previous equation forces qπ(K/CK(N)), and therefore a Sylow q-subgroup of K has order at least q2. In particular, for all non-nilpotent battens V of K, we have that B(V)CK(N). It follows that qπ(K)*. Now Lemma 7.10 provides X,Y{T,U,B}L such that XY and Oq(CK(N))XY=E. Since Oq(CK(N)) is characteristic in CK(NE NK=G, it follows that G/Oq(CK(N)) is not L10-free. Moreover, G/Oq(CK(N))L by Lemma 7.6. Since G is a minimal counterexample, we conclude that Oq(CK(N))=1. We recall that G is soluble, by Lemma 7.1, hence CK(N) is soluble, and then there must exist a prime qπ(CK(N)) such that Oq(CK(N))1. This gives a contradiction, and therefore CK(N)=1. □

We remark that, by (1), we may apply Lemmas 7.7 and 7.8.

(2) For all pπ(N) we have that Op(N)DEG. In particular ND \unlhdG and NE=1.

Proof. Let H{E,D}, let pπ(N) and set P:=Op(N). If H = E, then we set M:={U,T,B} and otherwise we set M:={A,B,C}. Then for all distinct X,YM, we have that XY=H and X,Y=F.

Assume for a first contradiction that HP is not a normal subgroup of G. Since every subgroup of N is normal in N by (1), it follows that K does not induce power automorphism on P. Then Lemma 5.4 implies that K acts irreducibly on P˜:=[P,K]/Φ([P,K]). We apply Lemma 7.11 twice to find some XM and some YM{X} such that X and Y act irreducibly on P˜. In particular [P,K]=[HP,Y]=[HP,X]XY=H. It follows that [P,K]HP[P,K]CP(K), which yields that HP is normalized by K and hence HPENK=G. This is a contradiction. We deduce that PD EG as stated, in particular ND EG and also NE EG.

For the final statement in (2) we use that G/(NE) is not L9-free. Then the minimality of G and Lemma 7.6 give that NE=1. □

(3) For every qπ(K) such that 1QSylq(D), one of the following holds:

[N,Ω1(Q)]DA or K induces power automorphisms on [N,Ω1(Q)] and [N,Ω1(Q)]A1.

Moreover E = 1.

Proof. We adopt the same notation as in the previous step, which means that H{E,D}pπ(N) and P:=Op(N). If H = E, then M:={U,T,B}, and otherwise M:={A,B,C}. Whenever X,YM are distinct, then XY=H and X,Y=F.

Let qπ(K)π(H) and QSylq(D). By conjugation we may suppose that QK. Then Ω1(Q)=Ω1(Q0) for some Sylow q-subgroup Q0 of K by Lemmas 2.6 and 7.7 provides some pπ(N) such that 1[N,Ω1(Q)] is a p-group. Now Lemma 7.8 (e) states that X=(XP)NX(Ω1(Q)) for all subgroups XM (*).

Let X and Y be distinct elements of M and assume for a contradiction that XP and YP are subgroups of CP(K). Then G=(1)F=X,Y()CP(K),NX(Ω1(Q)),NY(Ω1(Q))CP(K)NG(Ω1(Q))=NG(Ω1(Q)),which contradicts (1).

For the remainder of this proof we let X and Y in M be such that their intersection with P is not contained in CP(K). We note that CP(K)=CP(Ω1(Q)) by Lemma 5.5. Then it follows that 1[PX,Ω1(Q)]=[[PX,Ω1(Q)],Ω1(Q)] and hence [P,K]XCP(K). In a similar way we observe that [P,K]YCP(K).

If K acts irreducibly on [P,K]/Φ([P,K]), then Lemma 7.11 yields that X or Y, say X, acts irreducibly on [P,K]/Φ([P,K]). It follows that [P,K]X and [P,K]YXY=H. Let ZM{X,Y}. Then Lemma 7.11 yields that Z or Y, say Y, acts irreducibly on [P,K]/Φ([P,K]) and contains [P,K]Y. Since [P,K]YCP(K), it follows that [P,K]VX=H. By (1), this is only possible if H = D, in other words π(K)π(E)=. Then the fact that EN=1 (see (1) once more) forces E = 1.

The previous paragraph also gives that [N,Ω1(Q)]=[P,Ω1(Q)]=[P,K]DA, by Lemma 5.4, in the case where K acts irreducibly on [P,K]/Φ([P,K]).

Otherwise Lemma 5.4 gives that K and hence Ω1(Q) induce power automorphisms on P. Together with (1) this means that every subgroup of P is normal in G. Now, if V,WM are distinct, then PNG(P)=G=V,W()(VP)(WP)NG(Ω1(Q))and it follows that P=(VP)(WP). We deduce that |P|=|VP|·|WP||HP| for all W,VM. In particular |WP|=|XP|1 for all WM. This implies all our claims about D, because P=[P,K]=[P,Ω1(Q)]=[N,Ω1(Q)] by Lemma 5.4 and AM.

If, still in the power automorphism case, we have that H = E, then we recall that EP=1 by (1). Therefore |(UP)|·|(TP)|=|(UP)|·|(TP)||EP|=|(UP)(TP)|=|P|=|(UP)(AP)| =|UP|·|AP||PE|=|UP|·|AP|.

This implies that AP=TP1. But in this case we may interchange T by S in M. Since 1TP=AP=SP, we arrive at the contradiction that 1STP=EPEN=1 (by (1)). Thus, we have that π(K)π(E)= in this case as well. Again it follows that E = 1. □

The remainder of the proof is dedicated to constructing a subgroup of G that violates Property (L4).

(4) If pπ(N), then AK does not centralize Op(N). In particular AK1.

Proof. We assume for a contradiction that AK centralizes P:=Op(N) for some pπ(N).

It follows from Lemma 7.3 that, for every subgroup X of G=POp(N)K, there is some xP such that X(XP)Op(N)Kx. Since [P,AK]=1, we further have THAT X(XP)Op(N)Ky for all XA and yP (*).

Assume that AP=1. Then for both X{U,B}, we see that PG=(1)F=U,A()(PX)Op(N)Kx and therefore P=PU=PBUB=E. But this contradicts (3).

Thus AP1 and then (1), together with our assumption at the beginning of the proof, imply that every subgroup of AP is normal in A. Suppose that X,Y{S,T,D} are distinct. We recall that APA=X,Y(XP)(YP)Op(N)K, and then it follows that AP=(XP)(YP). Since XY=E=(2)1, we know more: TPSPDP and |TP|2=|AP|.

If K induces power automorphisms on P and if X{A,T,S}, then (XP) and (UP) are normal subgroups of G by (1). In addition there is some uP such that U(UP)Op(N)Ku and then X(XP)Op(N)Ku by (*). We apply Lemma 7.9 to see that |PA|=|P:PU|=|PS|=|PA|. Now it follows that PA=1, which is a contradiction.

We conclude that K does not induce power automorphisms on P. Then Lemma 5.4 gives that K acts irreducibly on [P,K]/Φ([P,K]). Since PDEG by (2), we see that either [P,K]D or that 1PDCP(K).

In the first case TPDP[P,K] and TD=E=(2)1. This implies, together with Lemma 1.1, that CP(K) has a subgroup isomorphic to [P,K]. We apply Lemma 5.4, in combination with Part (b) of Lemma 4.17, and we deduce that [P,K] is cyclic of order 2 and that, therefore, K centralizes it. This is impossible.

It follows that the second case holds, i.e. 1PDCP(K). Then p = 2 by Corollary 5.6 (a). If [P,K] is not elementary abelian, then Part (b) of Lemmas 4.17 and 5.4 give that [P,K]Q8 and P=[P,Q]×I, where I is a subgroup of P of order at most 2. We note that TPDP and TD=E=(3)1, and then we conclude that TP and DP are cyclic of order 2. Consequently AP=(TP)·(DP)=Ω1(P)EG. Now 1=(3)E=UAUΩ1(P) and therefore UOπ(N)Ku. We arrive at a contradiction: PG=U,A(PA)Oπ(N)Ku, because [P,K]Q8 is not elementary abelian.

So we finally have that [P,K] is elementary abelian. Then Lemma 4.17(b) gives that CP(K) is cyclic and Lemma 1.1 shows that TPDPCP(K).

Together with the fact that TD=E=(3)1, we obtain that DP is cyclic of order 2. It follows that PDTP and PS have order 2 and hence PA is elementary abelian of order 4. Moreover A[P,K] is cyclic of order 2, and therefore it equals one of the subgroups TPSP or DP. The last case is not possible because DPCP(K). By symmetry between S and T in the lattice we may suppose that TP[P,K]. Recall that K acts irreducibly on [P,K] while AK centralizes P. In particular (1) implies that A does not act irreducibly on [P,K]. Thus Lemma 7.11, together with the fact that G=(1)F=A,U, gives that U acts irreducibly on [P,K]. We also know that TU=E=(3)1, and this implies that [P,K]U. Then Lemma 1.2 yields that UPCP(K). But we recall that CP(K) is cyclic, and its unique involution is contained in D. Then the fact that UD=E=(3)1 implies that UP=1. Finally, we see that G=(1)F=U,T()[P,K]Op(N)Ku, which gives a contradiction. □

By conjugation and by Lemma 7.3 we may suppose that A=(AN)(AK).

We set π:=π(K)*π(A) and we let L1 be a Hall π-subgroup of AK.

Then we let σ:={pπ(N)|[Op(N),Q]1 for some QL1, where |Q|π}.

(5) If pπ(N) and [Op(A),L1]=1, then Op(N)D. Moreover πσ.

Proof. First suppose that L1 centralizes P:=Op(N) for some pπ(N). Then (4) implies that AKL1 and then there is a non-nilpotent batten V of K such that Q:=B(V)A and [P,Q]1. Now |Q|=q is a prime and [N,Q]=[P,Q] by Lemma 7.7. In addition we see, from Definition 4.16, that Q does not induce power automorphisms on P and that P=[P,Q]. If q divides |D|, then (3) implies that P=[N,Q]D, as stated.

Now we suppose that q does not divide |D|. Let RK be such that V = QR. Up to conjugation we may suppose that RL1 is a Sylow subgroup of L1. Then R does not centralize P by Definition 5.1 and hence RL1. It follows that RA, from the definition of L1. Since Q·Φ(R)=Q·Z(V) is nilpotent by Lemma 2.5, we deduce that A has a normal q-complement. Moreover AL, by Lemma 7.4, whence we may apply Lemma 7.10 to A. Then we see that S and T have orders divisible by q, because qπ(D). Let t,s[P,Q] be such that QsS and QtT. The irreducible action of Q on P, together with the fact that PTSE=(3)1, implies that PT=1 or PS=1. Without loss PT=1. Then TNG(Qt) by Lemma 7.8 (e). Assume that A normalizes Qt. Then QsNG(Qt), which implies that [ts1,Q]Qs=Qs,QtNG(Qt) by Lemma 4.1.1 (b) of [Citation7]. Then the irreducible action of Qt on P forces t = s, contradicting the fact that TS=E=(3)1.

Thus A does not normalize Qt and T,D=ANG(Qt), which yields that DNG(Qt)=(Op(N)K)×CP(K)=Op(N)K by Part (a) of Lemma 7.8. It follows that DP1 and therefore PD, because PDEG by (2) and K acts irreducibly on P.

We turn to the second statement and assume for a contradiction that π=π(A)π(K)=. Then AK=1, contrary to (4). Hence if π=π(A)π(K)*=, then we can draw two conclusions: First L1=1 and the statement we just proved gives that ND. Second, there must be a prime in π(K)π(K)* dividing |A|. By definition of π(K)*, such a prime is |B(V)| for some non-nilpotent batten V of K. We choose such a non-nilpotent batten V and set Q:=B(V). Then there are some prime r and an r-subgroup RK such that QR = V, and rπ(K)* because of the structure of non-nilpotent battens (Definition 2.1). In particular r|A| by assumption and Lemma 7.10 yields that B and U contain a conjugate of R. We recall that NDB by the first consequence of our assumption and because of the structure of the lattice L9. Then Lemma 7.8(c) gives that Ω1(R)GB. Thus BU=E=(3)1, which is a contradiction. This proves that π.

If σ=, then for all pπ(N), all qπ and all q-subgroups Q of L1, we have that [Op(N),Q]=1. Then [N,L1]=1 by definition of L1, and L11 because π. But then 1L1CK(N), contrary to (1). □

Next we set H:=Oσ(N) and we prove that H is a candidate for the desired properties in (L4).

(6) The non-trivial Sylow subgroups of H are elementary abelian (in particular N is abelian), but not cyclic, and KPotK(H).

Proof. By definition HN is nilpotent. If, for all pσ, the group K does not act irreducibly on [Op(N),K]/Φ([Op(N),K]), then Lemma 5.4 gives that KPotK(H). In particular Op(N) is not cyclic. Moreover, Corollary 5.6 yields that Op(N)=[Op(N),K] is elementary abelian. Therefore, our claim is satisfied in this case.

Let us assume for a contradiction that there is some pσ such that K acts irreducibly on the group [Op(N),K]/Φ([Op(N),K]). We set P:=Op(N) and we choose QL1 of order qπ such that [P,Q]1, by the definition of σ.

Case 1: [P,Q]A.

Then Lemma 7.8(c) implies that QgA for every gG. We recall that UA=E=(3)1, and then it follows first that qπ(U) and then that q||B|, by Lemma 7.10. Here we use that G=F=B,U by (1). Thus we find some gG such that QgD, because D=AB. We apply (3) to observe that [P,Q]=[N,Q]D and then D contains every conjugate of Q by Lemma 7.8(c). Recall that qπ(U), which implies that qπ(T) by Lemma 7.10. Again we use that G=F=T,U. But this contradicts the fact that TD=E=1 by (3).

Case 2: [P,Q]A.

Then [P,Q]D, in particular PD, and PDEG by (2). This means that K stabilizes the subgroup [PD,K]/ of [P,K]/Φ([P,K]), while acting irreducibly. This forces [PD,K]Φ([P,K]), and together with coprime action (Lemma 1.1) we see that K centralizes PD.

By Lemma 7.3 we know that AL, with type (AN,AK). Additionally, since qπ(K)*, the group K has a normal q-complement. Then AK also has a normal q-complement. We may apply Lemma 7.10 to A=T,S=T,D=S,D. It yields that at least two of the groups D, T, S have a subgroup of order |Q|. As |Q||E| by (2), there is some gG such that QgQ and QgA. Then Part (e) of Lemma 7.8 implies that PACP(Q)=CP(K) by Lemma 5.5. In the present case we have that [P,A]A, and then Lemma 1.2 gives that A does not act irreducibly on [P,K]/Φ([P,K]). Thus AK induces power automorphism on P by Lemma 5.4, and these automorphisms are not trivial because QAK. Corollary 5.6 (c) implies that P=[P,AK]=5.4[P,K] is elementary abelian and in particular that DPCP(K)=5.5CP(AK)=1. Hence there is some d[P,K] such that D=ND(Qd), by Lemma 7.8(b). In addition we see from Lemma 7.11 that B and C act irreducibly on P. If it was true that PB, then it would follow that 1PAPBAPDCP(K)=1, which is a contradiction. We conclude that PB and hence PB=1 because of the irreducible action of B on P, and similarly PC=1.

Then Lemma 7.8(b) provides b,cP such that B=NB(Qb) and C=NC(Qc). If Qb=Qc, then G=F=B,CNG(Qb), which is false.

Consequently QbQc, and we can use Lemma 7.8(a), Dedekind’s modular law and Lemma 1.4(c). Together this shows that DNB(Qb)NC(Qc)=Op(N)KbOp(N)Kc=Op(N)(KbOp(N)Kc)Op(N)CK(bc1)CG(bc1),because N is nilpotent and because (bc1)KOp(N)POp(N)=1.

We recall that P=[P,K] is abelian, hence it is contained in Z(N), and then it follows that D centralizes 1bc1[P,K]. Here we also use Lemma 5.4, i.e. that D centralizes P. We conclude that D=ND(Qh) for all hP. Again Lemma 7.8(b) provides t,sP such that T=(TP)NT(Qt) and S=(TS)NC(Qs). Let X{T,S}. Then PAA=D,X(XP)NG(Qx), which implies that PX=PA. But now PAPST=PE=1, by (3), which gives a final contradiction. □

(7) For all pσ we have that Op(N)A1.

Proof. We set P:=Op(N) for some pσ. Then there is some QL1 of order qπ such that [P,Q]1, by the definition of σ. Then qπ(K)* and we see that K as well as KA have a normal q-complement. Since AL by Lemma 7.4, we may apply Lemma 7.10. We notice that A=D,T=D,S, and then it follows that qπ(D) or that qπ(T)π(S). In the first case (3) implies our assertion. In the second case we use Lemma 7.8(c). It gives that QsS and QtT for some t,s[P,K]. We deduce that [t1s,Q]Qs,QtA by Lemma 4.1.1 of [Citation7]. In conclusion, our assertion is true or t1s centralizes Q. But in the second case, we see that Qt=QsTS=E=(3)1, and this gives a contradiction. □

(8) For all qπ we have that q divides |S||T|, and |B|.

Furthermore, if QL1 and |Q|=q, then [N,Q]T=[N,Q]S=1, but [N,Q]U1.

Proof. Suppose that QL1 has order q. Then [N,Q] is a p-group by Lemma 7.7, for some prime pσ. We set P=Op(N). Then for every X{T,S} there is some xP such that X=(XP)NX(Qx), by Lemma 7.8(b). Using (6) we see that K induces power automorphisms on P. Thus P=[P,K] is elementary abelian by Corollary 5.6(c), and then Lemma 7.9 is applicable.

Assume for a contradiction that P(PA)(PU). Then, for all X{T,S,A}, we have that PX,U=PF=(1)P>(PA)(PU)(PX)(PU).

Hence Lemma 7.9 yields that |P|=|(PX)(PU)|p=(2)|(PX)||(PU)|p and, for all X{T,S,A}, we see that p·|PX|=|P:PU|. In particular, we have that |PA|=|PS|=|PT|. Therefore, the fact that T,SA implies that PA=PT=PSP(TS)=PE=(3)1. This contradicts (7).

We conclude that P=(PA)(PU) and hence Lemma 7.9 provides some element gP such that, for both X{A,U}, it is true that X(XP)Op(N)Kg=(XP)NG(Q)g.

Assume for a contradiction that qπ(U). Then Part (e) of Lemma 7.8 yields that QgAU=E=(3)1. This is impossible. Thus qπ(U) and we deduce that qπ(X) for all X{T,S,B}. Here we use Lemma 7.10 and the fact that G=(1)F=U,X. Next we apply Lemma 7.9, which gives that (PA)(PS)(PT). Then the same lemma yields, for both combinations of {X,Y}{T,S}, that p divides |PY||PX||PU|=|PA||PU|=|P||PX||PU|·p.

It follows that p·|PY|p and then that SP=TP=1. Finally (6) and Lemma 7.9 yield that p2|P||PT||PU|·p=|PU|·p. We conclude that PU1. □

(9) For every pσ there is some rπ(K)* such that a Sylow r-subgroup of U does not centralize Op(N).

Proof. We set P:=Op(N). Since pσ, there is some QL1 such that |Q|=qπ. In addition (6) implies that P is elementary abelian, and then PZ(N) because N is nilpotent. By Lemma 7.8(b) and (8) there is some sP such that S=NS(Qs).

Assume for a contradiction that U centralizes P. Then U=Us=(UP)NU(Qs) by Lemma 7.8(d) and hence G=(1)F=U,S(UP)NG(Qs) implies that UP=P. With (7) we obtain the contradiction that 1PAUA=E=(3)1.

It follows that U does not centralize P. We recall that PZ(N) and then we obtain a prime rπ(K) such that a Sylow r-subgroup of U does not centralize P. Since K induces power automorphisms on P by (6), Definition 5.1 gives, for every non-nilpotent batten V of K, that B(V) centralizes P. This implies that rπ(K)*. □

We are now able to define L and J. Let uN be such that U=(UN)(UKu).

We set π˜:={rπ(K)*|[H,R]1 for someRSylr(U)} and we let L2 be a Hall π˜-subgroup of (Uu1K). Then L2K and L=L1,L2 is a subgroup of K. In addition (5) and (9) show that π˜.

Next we set ρ:={pπ(N)|[Op(N),R]1 for some RL2 with |R|π˜} and J:=[Oρ(N),K]. Then ρ by Lemma 7.7, because π˜, and hence J1. Finally, we note that J is L-invariant by construction.

(10) σρ=, i.e. |H| and |J| are coprime.

Proof. We assume for a contradiction that the prime p divides |H| and |J|. Then by definition there are qπ and rπ˜ and subgroups QL1 and RL2 such that the following hold:

|Q|=q|R|=r1[N,Q]Op(N)=:P and 1[N,R]P.

In particular (6) shows that K induces power automorphisms on P. It follows from Corollary 5.6 (c) and Lemma 5.4 that P=[P,K]=[P,Q]=[N,Q]=[N,R], and then (8) shows that PS=1. Moreover PA1 by (7). We apply Lemma 7.9 to obtain some i,j{1,0} such that pi|PU|=|(PU)(PS)|pi=|P|=|(PU)(PA)|pj=(2)|(PU)||(PA)|pj.

This implies that |PA|pj=pi, and we obtain that i = 1 and j = 0.

In particular we see that P=(UP)(AP). Then Lemma 7.9 and the fact that AU=E=(3)1 give some element gP such that X(PX)Kg=(PX)NG(R)g, where X{A,U}. Assume for a contradiction that rπ(A). Then 7.8(d) forces RgUA=E=(3)1. This is impossible, hence rπ(A) and we apply Lemma 7.10 to G=(1)F=A,B. Then it follows that rπ(B).

Moreover qπ(B)π(T) by (8). Since BT=E=(3)1, this is not possible, hence Lemma 7.9 and (8) give that |P|=|PB|·|PT|·p=|PB|·p. On the other hand we have that rπ(B)π(U), which is also impossible because BU=E=(3)1. Now Lemma 7.9 implies that |PU|·|PB|·p=|P|=|PB|·p. In particular we see that PU=1, and this contradicts (8). □

We summarize:

The definitions of σ and H imply that HN, and (6) shows that the non-trivial Sylow subgroups of H are not cyclic. In addition LK induces power automorphisms on H.

From (10) we deduce that ππ˜=. A Hall π(K)*-subgroup of K is nilpotent by Lemma 2.7, which means that L is nilpotent. In particular we see that L=L1×L2. Let rπ(L)=ππ˜ and R=Or(L). If rπ, then [H,R][[N,Ω1(R)],R]1, and if rp˜, then [H,R]1 by (9). These arguments show that π(L)=π(L/CL(H)) (*).

We assume for a contradiction that L is not cyclic. Then, since L is nilpotent and a batten group by Lemma 2.7, we deduce that O2(L)Q8. Definition 4.8 implies that, for all pπ(N), the group O2(L) does not induce non-trivial power automorphisms on Op(N). In particular O2(L) centralizes H, which contradicts (*). Thus L is cyclic.

Furthermore, we already saw that J is L-invariant and that 1J. Then (10) gives that (|H|,|J|)=1, and since N is nilpotent, this forces [H,J]=1.

Assume for a contradiction that J is not abelian. Then Lemma 4.17(b) and Lemma 5.4 show that O2(J)=[O2(N),K]Q8 and therefore 2ρ. We let rπ˜ be such that a Sylow r-subgroup R of K acts faithfully on O2(J). Then we must have that |R|=3 because O2(J)Q8. Moreover Lemma 7.8(a) yields that R centralizes O2(N)H. This contradicts (*).

Hence J is abelian. For every qπ and every subgroup QL1 of order q, the definition of σ and Lemma 7.7 provide some pσ such that [N,Q]Op(N)=P. Then we see, using (6) and Corollary 5.6, that CP(Q)=1. Furthermore (10) yields that Q centralizes J=Oρ(N), and then it follows that 1=CP(Q)CP(CL(J)). Since H=Oσ(N) is abelian, we conclude that CH(CL(J))=1.

The previous argument also yields that {qπ(L)|COq(L)(H)<COq(L)(J)}π. Let rπ˜ and suppose that RL has order r. We recall the definition of ρ and apply Lemma 7.7: Then we see that 1[N,R]Oρ(N)=J. Thus r{qπ(L)|COq(L)(H)<COq(L)(J)} and it follows that {qπ(L)|COq(L)(H)<COq(L)(J)}=π.

Since GL, we can use Property (L4), which gives some g(HJ)# that centralizes Oπ(L)=:L1 or Oπ(L)=:L2. Let i{1,2} be such that [Li,g]=1. We may suppose that g has prime order p. Then pσρ and hence there is a subgroup QL of prime order such that [N,Q]Op(N)=:P. Lemma 5.5 gives that gCP(Li)=CP(K) or that Li centralizes P.

In the first case Corollary 5.6 yields that p = 2, and then K does not induce power automorphisms on P. Using (6) we deduce that pρ and gOp(J)CP(K)=[P,K]CP(K)J. Since J is abelian, we obtain a contradiction in this case.

It follows that the second case above holds, i.e. [P,Li]=1. This means that i = 1 if pρ and i = 2 if pσ. In addition we see, from (9), that i2. We conclude that Li=L1pρ and qπ. In particular qπ(A). Since G=(1)F=A,U=A,B, Lemma 7.10 implies that B and U contain a conjugate of Q. In addition (5) shows that PDB and therefore Lemma 7.8(c) gives that QGB. Finally, we obtain a contradiction, because BU=E=1 by (3). This concludes the proof. □

Main Theorem. A finite group is in L if and only if it is L9-free.

Proof. Let G be a finite group. If G is L9-free, then Theorem 6.5 shows that GL.

Conversely, if GL, then G is L9-free by Theorem 8.1. □

References

  • Andreeva, S., Schmidt, R., Toborg, I. (2011). Lattice-defined classes of finite groups with modular Sylow subgroups. J. Group Theory 14:747–764. DOI: 10.1515/jgt.2010.075.
  • Baginski, C., Sakowicz, A. (1998). Finite groups with globally permutable lattice of subgroups. Colloq. Math. 82: 65–77. DOI: 10.4064/cm-82-1-65-77.
  • Huppert, B. (1967). Endliche Gruppen I. Berlin: Springer.
  • Iwasawa, K. (1941). Ueber endliche Gruppen und die Verbaende ihrer Untergruppen. J. Fac. Sci. Imp. Univ. Tokyo I(4):171–199.
  • Kurzweil, H., Stellmacher, B. (1998). Theorie der endlichen Gruppen. Berlin: Springer.
  • Pölzing, J., Waldecker, R. (2015). M9-free groups. J. Group Theory 18:155–190. DOI: 10.1515/jgth-2014-0034.
  • Schmidt, R. (1994). Subgroup Lattices of Groups. Berlin: de Gruyter.
  • Schmidt, R. (2003). L-free groups. Illinois J. Math. 47(1/2):515–528. DOI: 10.1215/ijm/1258488169.
  • Schmidt, R. (2007). L10-free groups. J. Group Theory 10:613–631.
  • Schmidt, R. (2010). L10-Free {p, q}-groups. Note Mat. 30:55–72.